College of William & Mary Law School
William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository
Faculty Publications Faculty and Deans
2019
Right on Time: First Possession in Property and
Intellectual Property
Dotan Oliar
James Y. Stern
William & Mary Law School, jyst[email protected]
Copyright c 2019 by the authors. 3is article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository.
h4ps://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs
Repository Citation
Oliar, Dotan and Stern, James Y., "Right on Time: First Possession in Property and Intellectual Property" (2019). Faculty Publications.
1906.
h4ps://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs/1906
395
RIGHT ON TIME: FIRST POSSESSION IN PROPERTY AND
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
DOTAN OLIAR & JAMES Y. STERN
A
BSTRACT
How should we allocate property rights in unowned tangible and intangible
resources? This Article develops a model of original acquisition that draws
together common law doctrines of first possession with original acquisition
doctrines in patent, copyright, and trademark law. The common denominator is
time: in each context, doctrine involves a trade-off between assigning
entitlements to resources earlier or later in the process of their development and
use. Early awards risk granting exclusivity to parties who may not be capable
of putting resources to their best use. Late awards prolong contests for
ownership, which may generate waste or discourage acquisition efforts in the
first place. While the doctrinal resolution of these timing questions varies in
different resource contexts, the determination depends upon a recurring and
discrete set of functional considerations. This Article applies its theory to assess
a host of doctrinal features in our patent, copyright, and trademark laws, to
analyze recent intellectual property law developments, and to suggest directions
for reform.
Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law and Associate Professor of Law,
William & Mary Law School, respectively. We thank Avi Bell, Hanoch Dagan, John Duffy,
Peter Menell, Gideon Parchomovsky, Ariel Porat, Betsy Rosenblatt, George Rutherglen, and
Paul Stephan, as well as participants at the 2017 meeting of the American Law & Economics
Association, the Intellectual Property Scholars Conference, the Property Works-In-Progress
Conference, and the UCLA Faculty Workshop for useful comments and suggestions. © 2019
Dotan Oliar & James Y. Stern.
396 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
CONTENTS
I
NTRODUCTION ............................................................................................... 397
I. FIRST POSSESSION: FORMS AND FUNCTIONS ............................................. 404
II. ORIGINAL ACQUISITION IN INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY .............................. 417
A. Patent ........................................................................................... 420
B. Trademark ................................................................................... 428
C. Copyright ..................................................................................... 435
III. GRASPING POSSESSION ............................................................................ 440
A. Doctrinal Implications ................................................................. 440
1. Patent Trolls: Of Abstract Ideas and IPRs ............................. 440
2. The Hunt for Secondary Meaning ......................................... 444
B. Institutional Implications ............................................................. 446
1. Possession, Information, and Intellectual Property ............... 446
2. Intellectual Property as Property: Flexibility and
Standardization ...................................................................... 451
C. Theoretical Implications .............................................................. 453
1. On Defining IP Goods ........................................................... 453
2. Divided Possession Rules ...................................................... 456
CONCLUSION ................................................................................................... 457
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 397
INTRODUCTION
Time is central to intellectual property (“IP”) law. Congress, courts, and
scholars rightfully give considerable attention to questions about when IP rights
should end,
1
but there is comparatively little analysis of when they should begin.
While ownership of IP rights might be expected to start at original acquisition
through creation
2
or use,
3
matters are not quite so simple.
The foundation of ownership is first possession. Though some treat this as a
normative or philosophical proposition,
4
this Article means it in a positive,
practical sense. Ordinarily, someone comes to own something by acquiring title
from someone else who owned it, who acquired title from someone else who
owned it before that, and so on, until one gets back to the very first owner and
the so-called “root” of title.
5
But how did the first owner come to own it? How,
in other words, do things come to be owned?
6
The basic answer property law
gives is first possession: ownership of an unowned resource goes to whomever
does something referred to as “possessing” it before anyone else.
7
1
See U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 8 (empowering Congress to secure IP rights that last for
“limited [t]imes”); 15 U.S.C. § 1127 (2012) (defining “abandoned” trademark as among other
things, when mark becomes a generic name for goods it designates); 17 U.S.C. § 302(a)
(2012) (stating that copyrights of individual authors generally expire seventy years after
author’s death); 35 U.S.C. § 154(2) (2012) (stating that patents generally expire twenty years
after they are applied for); Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 189 (2003) (upholding
constitutionality of copyright term after it was extended by twenty years against arguable
violation of “limited [t]imes” clause); W
ILLIAM D. NORDHAUS, INVENTION, GROWTH, AND
WELFARE: A THEORETICAL TREATMENT OF TECHNOLOGICAL CHANGE 76-80 (1969) (providing
canonical theoretical framework for setting optimal patent term).
2
See 17 U.S.C. § 102 (stating that copyrights are generally granted to whoever fixes
original work of authorship in physical object); 35 U.S.C. § 101 (stating that patents are
generally granted to whoever invents any new and useful invention).
3
Trademarks have long been awarded to whoever was the first to merely adopt and use a
mark in commerce. See Hydro-Dynamics, Inc. v. George Putnam & Co., 811 F.2d 1470, 1473
(Fed. Cir. 1987) (“The requirements of both adoption and use devolve from the common law;
trademark rights in the United States are acquired by such adoption and use . . . .); see also
15 U.S.C. § 1127 (defining “use in commerce” as “bona fide use of a mark in the ordinary
course of trade”).
4
See, e.g., JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT 306 (Peter Laslett ed.,
Cambridge Univ. Press 1960) (1690) (“He that is nourished by the Acorns he pickt up under
an Oak, or the Apples he gathered from the Trees in the Wood, has certainly appropriated
them to himself. . . . I ask then, When did they begin to be his? . . . And ‘tis plain, if the first
gathering made them not his, nothing else could.”).
5
See Carol M. Rose, Possession as the Origin of Property, 52 U. CHI. L. REV. 73, 73
(1985).
6
See id. (theorizing why certain actions, namely possession, allow one to obtain ownership
of things).
7
See 2 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *3 (noting that “whoever was in
occupation of any determinate spot of [ground] . . . acquired for the time a sort of ownership”);
398 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
Modern readers may be tempted to dismiss first possession as an essentially
antiquarian topic, given that so much of the tangible substance of the planet is
already owned, but the temptation should be resisted.
8
There are a number of
reasons why an understanding of first possession remains valuable, and this
Article concentrates on one of particular significance: first possession is the
principal device used to award exclusive rights to the products of human
imagination and ingenuity—that is, in the field of intellectual property.
9
This is
no small matter. In recent years, more than one million new IP rights have been
registered with the U.S. government annually, reflecting claims to everything
from pharmaceutical drugs to pop songs and from product logos to computer
code,
10
and many more have been created but not registered.
11
Information is the
most valuable resource of our age and the yet-to-be-owned expanses of human
creativity are seemingly endless. Attention to the rules allocating IP rights
remains critical.
Are we doing a good job propertizing creations of the mind? Do existing laws
and doctrines tend to “promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts,” the
constitutional aim of U.S. patent and copyright laws?
12
Or can these rules be
Dean Lueck, First Possession, in 2 NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW
132, 133-36 (Peter Newman ed., 1998) (describing first possession as rule which “grants an
ownership claim to the party that gains control before other potential claimants”).
8
The 1890 Census declared that the frontier region of the United States no longer existed.
See FREDERICK JACKSON TURNER, THE FRONTIER IN AMERICAN HISTORY 1 (1920) (“[A]t
present the unsettled area has been broken into by isolate bodies of settlement that there can
hardly be said to be a frontier line.”); Thomas W. Merrill, Accession and Original Ownership,
1
J. LEGAL ANALYSIS 459, 460 (2009) (suggesting principles of accession are primary
mechanism by which original title to property is established).
9
Cf. JOHN F. KENNEDY, “LET THE WORD GO FORTH”: THE SPEECHES, STATEMENTS, AND
WRITING OF JOHN F. KENNEDY 101 (Theodore C. Sorensen ed., 1988) (declaring “New
Frontier” beyond which “are the uncharted areas of science and space”).
10
For example, more than three hundred thousand patents were issued, and three hundred
thousand trademarks and four hundred thousand copyrights were registered in 2016, the last
year for which all statistics are available. See U.S.
COPYRIGHT OFFICE, FISCAL 2016 ANNUAL
REPORT 16 (2016), https://www.copyright.gov/reports/annual/2016/ar2016.pdf [https://perma
.cc/4XUA-C5YC] (stating that 414,269 copyrights were registered in 2016); U.S. P
ATENT &
TRADEMARK OFFICE, PERFORMANCE AND ACCOUNTABILITY REPORT 178, 193 (2016),
https://www.uspto.gov/sites/default/files/documents/USPTOFY16PAR.pdf [https://perma.cc
/GF8M-A77D] (stating that 334,107 patents were issued in 2016 and that 309,188 trademarks
were registered).
11
Copyrights and trademarks do not require registration as a prerequisite for their validity,
which depends only on fixation of an original work in a physical object or on the use of a
distinctive mark in commerce, respectively. See, e.g., 17 U.S.C. § 102(a) (2012); 15 U.S.C.
§ 1052(f) (2012).
12
U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 8; Dotan Oliar, Making Sense of the Intellectual Property
Clause: Promotion of Progress as a Limitation on Congress’s Intellectual Property Power,
94 GEO. L.J. 1771, 1845 (2006) (arguing that promotion of progress is not merely preambular
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 399
improved to better advance knowledge and human welfare? As the major
frontiers left for the human race to conquer increasingly become intangible, a
thorough understanding of the principles of first possession can help us perfect
our management of this legal frontier by implementing the lessons from the
common law’s long experience with the award of rights in physical resources.
This is particularly so in light of the special challenges that intangible resources
present. However difficult the concept of possession may sometimes be to apply
to physical goods,
13
it is immensely more complicated for “things” that exist
only in the mind’s eye. Custom and intuition provide less reliable safety nets,
making a good theoretical grip on the concept of possession particularly
valuable.
What, then, counts as first possession under traditional legal principles? For
centuries, the common law wrestled with the concept of possession and the
problem of defining those actions sufficient to confer rights in things that are
unowned.
14
The rule of first possession was applied across a broad swath of
resources, and the specific conduct qualifying as possession varied with the
nature of the resource.
15
Behavior as diverse as the snaring or killing of a wild
animal,
16
diverting a stream of water to farmland,
17
digging above a mineral
statement of purpose, but rather constitutional limitation subject to deferential standard of
review).
13
See, e.g., Popov v. Hayashi, No. 400545, 2002 WL 31833731, at *1, *2 (Cal. Super. Ct.
Dec. 18, 2002) (determining owner of historic home run ball when one individual had actual
possession, while another made substantial steps towards possession before being illegally
interfered with by a third party in his attempt).
14
See Rose, supra note 5, at 73 (“The law tells us what steps we must follow to obtain
ownership of things, but we need a theory that tells us why these steps should do the job.”).
15
John F. Duffy, Rethinking the Prospect Theory of Patents, 71 U. CHI. L. REV. 439, 447
(2004) (noting that although “rule-of-capture” is applied to both mining and patent claims,
application of rule varies with each subject).
16
See Pierson v. Post, 3 Cai. 175, 175 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1805) (holding that possession of
wild animal required capturing or mortally wounding it, rather than simply giving chase);
D
ALE D. GOBLE & ERIC T. FREYFOGLE, WILDLIFE LAW: CASES AND MATERIALS 98-100 (2002)
(describing early notions of property rights in hunting and capturing “beasts of the forest”).
17
See, e.g., Eddy v. Simpson, 3 Cal. 249, 251-52 (1853) (holding first possession of water
not to be possession of fluid itself, but rather its use).
400 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
deposit,
18
and viewing a sunken ship at the bottom of the ocean with a
submersible camera
19
have been treated as acts of possession.
20
As varied and idiosyncratic as these different actions may seem, patterns can
nevertheless be discerned. One of the clearest ways to make sense of the seeming
hodgepodge of possessory rules is to think about them in terms of a common
metric: time. Each of these possessory practices can usefully be placed on a
chronology starting with the first preliminary steps necessary to appropriate the
resource at issue and ending when the resource is consumed, commercialized,
or otherwise put to use.
21
The common law has tended to embrace either of two
approaches to first possession within the context of this chronology. One
recognizes an exclusive claim upon a resource when a claimant has undertaken
substantial investments and remains in hot pursuit—what this Article calls a
first-committed-searcher rule.
22
The other approach withholds any protection
until a claimant has somehow changed the resource in such a way that the
claimant is able to control and use it—what this Article calls a rule of capture.
23
This distinction between first possession rules in physical resources is key to
understanding original acquisition rules in IP law.
We begin by exploring the relative advantages and disadvantages of these
approaches in their application to tangible goods, setting out a framework to
analyze first possession questions. Prior scholarship noted many of the issues
18
See Union Oil Co. v. Smith, 249 U.S. 337, 346-48 (1919) (holding that while one
permissibly explores public lands for minerals, one has substantial interest in any minerals as
long as one puts forth persistent and diligent effort in ones prospecting).
19
See Columbus-America Discovery Grp. v. Atl. Mut. Ins., 974 F.2d 450, 465 (4th Cir.
1992) (holding that viewing sunken ship with submersible camera was sufficient to create
possessory interest in ship).
20
See Richard A. Epstein, The Allocation of the Commons: Parking on Public Roads, 31
J. LEGAL STUD. 515, 515 (2002) (analyzing how different systems of allocation in parking,
including possession of spaces, metered parking, and parking permits, effect formation and
transformation of property rights in parking spaces); Gregg W. Kettles, Formal Versus
Informal Allocation of Land in a Commons: The Case of the Macarthur Park Sidewalk
Vendors, 16 S.
CAL. INTERDISC. L.J. 49, 72-73 (2006) (discussing practices allocating
sidewalk spots to street vendors in Los Angeles).
21
See Arun S. Subramanian, Assessing the Rights of IRU Holders in Uncertain Times, 103
COLUM. L. REV. 2094, 2102-04 (2003) (asserting that most modern commentators view rights
of use, possession, and disposition as essential to establishing property rights); see also 26
U.S.C. § 7701(e)(1)(B) (2012) (identifying transfer of control as indicative of lease transfer);
Property, B
LACKS LAW DICTIONARY (10th ed. 2014) (defining property as right to possess,
use, and enjoy). Property has been defined as requiring “control over [an] item and an intent
to control it or to exclude others from it.” R
OGER BERNHARDT & ANN M. BURKHART, REAL
PROPERTY IN A NUTSHELL 4 (7th ed. 2016).
22
See WILLIAM M. LANDES & RICHARD A. POSNER, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY LAW 17 (2003).
23
See Lueck, supra note 7, at 135 (describing actual capture as “capturing or ‘reducing to
possession’ a flow from the asset”).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 401
that first possession rules present, but does so in a fragmented and often
unidirectional manner, with some commentators stressing the problems we
attribute to later awards and others stressing the problems we associate with
earlier ones.
24
What is missing is a comprehensive overview of the
considerations at play and an understanding of how these concerns relate to one
another and to the structure of first possession.
The essential tradeoff this Article identifies is as follows. On the one hand,
when exclusive rights vest early in the process of ultimate appropriation and use,
there is a risk those rights will be awarded to a party who will ultimately fail to
capture and use the resource.
25
On the other hand, when exclusive rights vest
late in the process, there is the danger either of a longer period of potentially
wasteful investment by parties competing to own the resource
26
or of potential
capturers opting to stay home because of the risk of losing investments prior to
capture—especially to free-riders profiting from the work they have done.
27
At
its core, first possession presents an ever-present tension between two recurring
sets of opposing concerns, one of which counsels in favor of earlier awards and
the other in favor of later ones. That tension does not necessarily result in a
stalemate, however, and its proper resolution in one context does not entail a
single solution to problems in all others. In different areas, the optimal timing of
an award of property rights is a function of the relative strength of these
countervailing concerns.
Elaborating on this tradeoff, this Article develops a framework to analyze and
evaluate the rules that govern the award of IP rights. In different areas within
our patent, copyright, and trademark systems, legal doctrine uses variants of the
two conceptions of the first possession rule to determine when exclusive rights
24
See supra notes 17-23 and accompanying text (discussing articles and cases that dealt
with some of respective problems with late and early rewards of possession).
25
See Columbia Motor Car Co. v. C. A. Duerr & Co., 184 F. 893, 904-11 (2d Cir. 1911)
(discussing controversial Selden patent, where Selden was awarded automobile patent before
Henry Ford, but court held that Ford did not infringe on patent due to Selden’s inferior
combination of automobile components and alleged lack of advancement of automobile
industry); U.S. Patent No. 549,160 (filed May 8, 1879). Other potential drawbacks of early
awards include the creation of incentives to carry out actions that are not ultimately necessary
to the ultimate deployment of the resource.
26
Yoram Barzel, Optimal Timing of Innovations, 50 REV. ECON. & STAT. 348, 348-49
(1968) (recognizing that “competition between potential innovators to obtain priority
rights . . . from innovations can result in premature applications of discoveries”).
27
Cf. Edmund W. Kitch, The Nature and Function of the Patent System, 20 J.L. & ECON.
265, 266 (1977) (viewing system which follows prospect theory of patents as set of
opportunities to pursue technological advances with associated set of probabilistic costs and
returns). Other potential costs include overinvestment in other aspects of the claiming process,
such as by inefficiently accelerating the process of development, as well as what might be
called anticompetitive behavior like secrecy and sabotage. See infra Part I (discussing first
possession rule).
402 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
are established and who among competing claimants should receive them. One
of the lessons that emerges from the study of IP doctrine is the dual function that
first possession rules play. Most obviously, first possession serves to resolve
disputes among rival contenders for exclusive rights in the same resource. But
first possession also sets the conditions for the acquisition of exclusive rights as
such, establishing what a person must do for exclusive rights to vest, whether in
tangible property or intellectual property.
28
The picture that emerges is complex, but modeling the rules governing the
award of IP rights in terms of first possession helps us understand those rules
and their implications more clearly. For example, many of the reforms
undertaken in response to what are thought to be abuses by so-called “patent
trolls” reflect an attempt to push the award of patent rights later in time.
29
This
suggests, on the one hand, that the patent troll problem is connected with early
awards of patent rights, and on the other hand, that policymakers should be
vigilant to ensure that the benefits of delaying the award of rights are compared
against the full range of the costs associated with later awards cataloged in the
discussion that follows.
Analogizing intellectual property to property is not free from difficulty,
30
and
the limits of our approach should be understood. The conceptual structure
borrowed from traditional property law can illuminate principles at work in IP
law. At the same time, however, the notion of intellectal property is an analogy,
not necessarily an identity. What this Article wishes to highlight here are
fundamental similarities with respect to the theory and doctrines of original
acquisition. This does not deny substantial theoretical and doctrinal differences
between property and intellectual property.
Modeling intellectual property with a possessory framework must be done
with sensitivity to differences in context. In the IP arena, concerns over notice
and information are much more pronounced than they are with respect to
tangible resources. Often, such concerns can be substantially mitigated through
the creation of registries and other notice mechanisms, and once in place, such
institutional devices may facilitate a more flexible approach to original
acquisition than might otherwise be feasible. The rules can more closely track
the idealized trade-off that shapes first possession doctrine, but they are also
more fluid because the nature of the claimable resources themselves is more up-
for-grabs. Not surprisingly, IP doctrine entails greater variation in the rules that
28
See infra notes 39-49 and accompanying text (reviewing criteria under which one may
gain exclusive rights through first possession).
29
See infra Part III.A.1.
30
Compare Mark A. Lemley, Property, Intellectual Property, and Free Riding, 83 TEX.
L. R
EV. 1031, 1032 (2005) (resisting notion that property law provides proper conceptual
framework for directing our thinking about IP law), with Frank H. Easterbrook, Intellectual
Property Is Still Property, 13 H
ARV. J.L. PUB. POLY 108, 118 (1990) (suggesting there is no
conceptual difference between tangible and intellectual property).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 403
set the time of a right’s award than does common-law property.
31
There are also
many instances in which IP doctrine changed the specific time at which
exclusive rights can be acquired. Sometimes, doctrinal change pushed that time
of acquisition earlier, such as in the case of intent to use applications in
trademark law, but other times later in time, such as in the case of the America
Invents Act. This variation, this Article suggests, has to do with the more
frequent changes in the relative costs and benefits of awarding rights earlier and
later in time, and of providing notice and administering exclusive rights in
information, in the dynamic market settings in which IP rights operate.
This Article is not the first academic work to explore the practical effects of
first possession rules,
32
but it is the first to develop a comprehensive account of
the major considerations that shape the doctrinal form of first possession and to
describe the design of first possession rules in terms of a consistent set of policy
tradeoffs between early and late awards of rights. Neither is this Article the first
to suggest parallels between IP doctrines and first possession
33
or to raise
questions about the timing of the award of IP rights.
34
It is, however, the first to
31
E.g., Leahy-Smith America Invents Act, Pub. L. 112-29, 125 Stat. 284, 329 (2011)
(codified as amended in scattered sections of 35 U.S.C.) (amending time in which patents
expire).
32
The leading article is Dean Lueck, The Rule of First Possession and the Design of the
Law, 38 J.L. & ECON. 393, 430-31 (1995) (observing effects of first possession rules on variety
of legal fields).
33
See Abraham Drassinower, Capturing Ideas: Copyright and the Law of First
Possession, 54 CLEV. ST. L. REV. 191, 191 (2006) (analogizing originality requirement in
copyright law to first possession requirement in property); Timothy R. Holbrook, Equivalency
and Patent Law’s Possession Paradox, 23 HARV. J.L. & TECH. 1, 4 (2009) (discussing
similarities and differences between patent and property law in applying principles of actual
and constructive possession); Timothy R. Holbrook, Patent Anticipation and Obviousness as
Possession, 65 E
MORY L.J. 987, 1035 (2016) (drawing parallel between enablement in patent
law and possession in property); Timothy R. Holbrook, Possession in Patent Law, 59 SMU
L. REV. 123, 175 (2006) (arguing that enablement is best means to demonstrate property-like
possession in patent law); Lisa Larrimore Oullette, Pierson, Peer Review, and Patent Law, 69
V
AND. L. REV. 1825, 1826 (2016) (comparing grant of possession in Pierson to more causal
standard applied in patent law which favors early chasers who put in little effort); Alfred C.
Yen, Restoring the Natural Law: Copyright as Labor and Possession, 51 OHIO ST. L.J. 517,
531 (1990) (outlining “basic copyright doctrines of originality and the idea/expression
dichotomy and then comparing them to the natural law of property through labor and
possession”).
34
See, e.g., Christopher A. Cotropia, The Folly of Early Filing in Patent Law, 61 HASTINGS
L.J. 65, 70 (2009) (criticizing legal incentives to file for patents early); Paul R. Gugliuzza,
Early Filing and Functional Claiming, 96 B.U.
L. REV. 1223, 1227 (2016) (noting
complexities and variables in determining optimal timing of patent issuance); Kitch, supra
note 27, at 285 (considering how awarding patents based on priority induces inefficiency in
early invention); Mark A. Lemley, Ready for Patenting, 96 B.U.
L. REV. 1171, 1186 (2016)
(noting problems with early filing on patent issuance).
404 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
undertake a systematic examination of first possession in IP law and to explicate
the similarities, and differences, in the functional considerations that underlie
first possession doctrines in physical property and across the three major areas
of IP law: patent, copyright, and trademark.
This Article proceeds in three stages. Part I outlines the role of first possession
doctrines in property law, pointing out differences in the way first possession is
approached in different contexts and discussing reasons for these differences. It
advances a general framework of original acquisition to guide inquiries into the
timing of property awards built around the characteristic tradeoffs that early and
late awards entail. Part II turns to intellectual property. It examines patent,
trademark, and copyright law to show how a variety of doctrines work together
in each of these fields to establish what is in effect a system based on original
acquisition. It points out ways in which the same core concerns first possession
rules present in the realm of tangible property illuminate the approach to the
award of IP rights. Part III steps back to engage in a more critical analysis, noting
ways in which existing doctrine gets things right and others in which it does not.
This Article concludes by considering the major themes that emerge from
considering the original acquisition concept as it plays out in the domain of
intellectual property, identifying lessons for both property and IP law.
I. F
IRST POSSESSION: FORMS AND FUNCTIONS
First possession is a bedrock principle of property law. Property regimes have
developed possessory claiming rules for the allocation of rights in all manner of
resources, ranging quite literally from diamonds
35
to dung.
36
Yet despite a
seemingly unitary doctrinal construct, important differences remain in the way
possession rules operate in different contexts. The key variable is time. Imagine
a chronology that begins with the first actions a person may take having any
relationship to a resource, like simply becoming aware of its existence or
forming an intent to use it. The timeline then proceeds through the various
actions necessary for a person to derive a benefit from the resource: preparations
for its pursuit; pursuit itself; the successful completion of pursuit by bringing the
resource within one’s control; cultivation and improvement to enable beneficial
use; and finally actual use, enjoyment, consumption of the resource, or its
transfer to another.
In theory, property law could have picked any point along this temporal
continuum as the one at which property rights vest. In practice, property law
essentially limited its choices to two. In some contexts, property law has deemed
“possession” to be satisfied at a comparatively early point in time. Under this
approach, possession occurs when a person has undertaken significant steps
toward the resource’s appropriation and use, even though actual control has not
yet been achieved. This Articles calls this variant of first possession a “first-
35
See Armory v. Delamirie (1722) 93 Eng. Rep. 664, 664 (KB).
36
Haslem v. Lockwood, 37 Conn. 500, 500 (1871).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 405
committed-searcher rule.”
37
Alternatively, and more commonly, property law
has deemed possession to be satisfied at a later point in time. Under this
approach, possession occurs only after a person has obtained control over the
resource. This Articles calls this variant of first possession a “rule of capture.”
38
These are very much ideal types, but they roughly represent two notional points
around which property law’s first possession doctrines tend to coalesce.
The property canon offers clear illustrations of each approach. Consider
Pierson v. Post,
39
a staple of first-year American property law curricula. The
case involved a hunter, Post, who chased a wild fox for some period of time,
only to lose the animal to a farmer, Pierson, who suddenly appeared on the scene
and quickly killed it.
40
The hunter sued the farmer to recover the value of the
animal’s pelt, but the court sided with the farmer.
41
The dissent argued that it
was enough to claim a wild animal if “the pursuer be within reach, or have a
reasonable prospect . . . of taking” it.
42
In our terms, it advocated awarding the
fox to the first committed searcher. The majority, however, rejected this course,
holding that “pursuit alone vests no property or right in the huntsman.”
43
In the
majority’s view, possession of wild animals required either “actual bodily
seizure” or having otherwise “wounded, circumvented or ensnared them, so as
to deprive them of their natural liberty, and subject them to the control of their
pursuer.”
44
The majority, in other words, held that first possession of foxes
would be satisfied only by the rule of capture.
A similar distinction can also be seen in the practices described in Professor
Robert Ellickson’s seminal study of nineteenth century whalers.
45
The usual rule
among whalers was analogous to the rule of capture adopted in Pierson v. Post:
A whaler establishes possession only after successfully lancing a whale with a
harpoon tethered and secured to the whaler’s boat.
46
The whale, in other words,
had to be brought under submission. This norm, known as the “fast-fish-loose-
37
See LANDES & POSNER, supra note 22, at 17 (stating that property law gives “first
committed searcher the exclusive right to conduct the search operation”).
38
See GOBLE & FREYFOGLE, supra note 16, at 98-99 (describing rule of capture based on
historical development through allocation of rights over wildlife).
39
3 Cai. 175 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1805).
40
Id. at 175.
41
Id. at 177-80.
42
Id. at 182 (Livingston, J., dissenting).
43
Id. at 177 (majority opinion).
44
Id. at 177-79.
45
See Robert C. Ellickson, A Hypothesis of Wealth-Maximizing Norms: Evidence from the
Whaling Industry, 5 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 83, 88-94 (1989) (discussing different property regime
norms in whaling industry).
46
See id. at 89-90 (“[The] rule was in practice likely to reward the first harpooner, who
had performed the hardest part of the hunt, as opposed to free riders waiting in the wings.”);
see also HERMAN MELVILLE, MOBY-DICK 305-06 (First Avenue 2014) (1851).
406 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
fish” rule, reflects a rule of capture approach to first possession of whales. But
some fisheries followed a first-committed-searcher approach. In waters
inhabited by the more aggressive sperm whale, custom granted an exclusive
claim to the first to lance a whale and mark its body with a harpoon, regardless
of whether the harpoon remained connected to the whaler’s vessel, so long as
the whaler remained in active pursuit.
47
In other words, a whaler could acquire
a claim to a whale at a stage prior to actual capture by making substantial
progress toward capture and demonstrating a commitment to following
through.
48
This norm, known as the “iron-holds-the-whale” rule, reflects a first-
committed-searcher approach to the first possession of whales.
49
The cases dealing with first possession suggest a recurring set of competing
practical considerations, some of which push for early awards of property rights
and some which push for late awards. Ideally, property doctrine would take
account of the relative strength of these considerations, which dictate the point
in time—or equivalently, the standard of performance—that should count as
satisfying the possession requirement with respect to a particular resource.
Figure 1 below illustrates the marginal benefits and costs of pushing back the
moment that is deemed to satisfy the possession requirement. Formally, the
optimal time to deem possession as having been established is the point where
the marginal benefit and marginal cost are equal. Differences in the way property
law approaches first possession can be understood as reflecting how the balance
between the relative pros and cons of early and late awards changes for different
resources along the course of their acquisition.
47
See Ellickson, supra note 45, at 90-92 (discussing “iron-holds-the-whale” property
norm, which required affixment of harpoon to whale coupled with fresh pursuit).
48
See Swift v. Gifford, 23 F. Cas. 558, 560 (D. Mass. 1872) (“[H]e who first strikes [the
whale] so effectually that the iron remains fast should have the better right, the pursuit still
continuing, it is reasonable, though merely conventional, and ought to be upheld.”).
49
See Ellickson, supra note 45, at 90-92. First-committed-searcher rules are frequently
coupled with a requirement that the claimant eventually complete capture before a durable
property right will be awarded. The primary role of the first-committed-searcher rule in these
situations is to provide the priority rule used to resolve disputes between two otherwise valid
claims, establishing the point in time used to resolve the contest between them.
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 407
Figure 1. Optimal Timing of Possession.
50
Marginal Benefit
(increased likelihood
of completion)
Marginal Cost
(discouragement &
competition waste)
t*
Time
Understanding this balance and the shift in equilibrium from one resource
context to another depends on an analysis of the competing forces that push in
favor of early and late awards. The magnitude of these concerns varies with
changes in factors such as the characteristics of the resources at issue, the ways
people desire to use them, the manner in which they are likely to be pursued,
and the technologies available to the legal system.
51
But the core concerns that
underlie this tradeoff are strikingly stable across the landscape of property law.
52
The principal danger of awarding rights too early in the development process
is the risk that they will go to someone who will fail to complete the proverbial
50
The curves are drawn schematically and need not be straight lines. While in many cases
it is reasonable to assume that the marginal benefit curve is downward sloping and that the
marginal cost curve is upward sloping, other depictions can fit equally well without any
significant change in the analysis. For example, the marginal cost curve may be flat. The only
essential assumption for the argument about a reasonably administrable optimal timing for
possession is that the marginal benefit curve initially lies above the marginal cost curve, and
that they intersect just once. When these assumptions are violated, first possession may not
be a suitable candidate for allocating property rights over previously unowned resources,
which is consistent with alternative social mechanisms for resource management, such as
common property or auctions. The discussion of such mechanisms is beyond the scope of this
Article.
51
Cf. Elinor Ostrom, Private and Common Property Rights, in 2 ENCYCLOPEDIA OF LAW
AND
ECONOMICS: CIVIL LAW AND ECONOMICS 332, 338 (Boudewijn Bouckaert & Gerrit De
Geest eds., 2000) (arguing that optimal strategy is to manage common property changes based
on given resource’s purpose of use, quantity, related technology, and other factors).
52
See infra note 69 and accompanying text (noting importance of property right timing to
optimize variety of resources).
408 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
chase, leaving the resource underused.
53
In such cases, it would have been better
to allow the ownership race to continue. The problem is essentially one of
misallocation. Awarding exclusive rights to a resource at an early stage when
considerable work must still be done to put the resource to use involves the
possibility that the resource will be awarded to someone who is not very good
at—and possibly incapable of—carrying out the tasks that still remain.
54
Late
awards can therefore be seen as a mechanism to identify the more capable, cost-
effective searchers.
When a party receives an early award but fails to follow through, the right can
sometimes be reallocated to a more capable party through voluntary exchange
or, perhaps, via abandonment and a new contest for possession.
55
Such
reallocations, however, will often be associated with transaction costs, which
may be prohibitive or otherwise entail significant waste, such as delay in the use
of the resource and search and negotiation costs associated with the reallocation
process itself.
56
Further, early awards may incentivize those who are incapable
of completing the chase but are able to take an early lead (deemed sufficient to
obtain a property right) to nevertheless join the race and do so.
57
But their hope
of profiting from such early lead may disincentivize more capable pursuers from
joining in. Paying to get the entitlement from the less capable yet early pursuer
would reduce their incentive to successfully complete the series of actions
necessary to bring the resource into its ultimate use.
On the other side of the ledger, a system in which rights are awarded later—
as under a rule of capture—presents two chief social costs. One is excessive and
wasteful investment in resource search and pursuit.
58
Efforts expended by those
53
See supra note 21 and accompanying text (discussing importance of timing when
conferring property interests); see also Eric R. Claeys, Exclusion and Exclusivity in Gridlock,
53 ARIZ. L. REV. 9, 10 (2011) (“[W]hen too many individuals have the rights to exclude in
relation to a resource, the resources may be underused.”).
54
See Lueck, supra note 32, at 394 (discussing critics who claim that early property awards
granted in homesteading, oil and gas extraction, and patent process encourage suboptimal
resource use and overexploitation).
55
See, e.g., Gary D. Libecap, Assigning Property Rights in the Common Pool:
Implications of the Prevalence of First-Possession Rules for ITQs in Fisheries, 22
MARINE
RESOURCES ECON. 407, 413 (2009) (noting that while first possession “rewards exploration
and risk taking,” later trade can “reallocate the resource to higher-valued users” and more
efficient uses).
56
See id. at 409.
57
Terry L. Anderson & Peter J. Hill, The Race for Property Rights, 33 J.L. & ECON. 177,
183-84 (1990) (discussing this phenomenon in context of squatters and speculators in land-
based property regimes).
58
See Lueck, supra note 32, at 402 (“[L]aws that rely on first possession tend to define
possession and grant ownership quite early to thwart wasteful investment.”); see also Barzel,
supra note 26, at 352 n.11 (suggesting that earlier grants of rights will prevent resources from
being wasted in course of competition); Duffy, supra note 15, at 443-44 (noting preference
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 409
who set out to capture a resource but are beaten by someone else are often
deadweight social loss, and to the extent later awards result in claimants having
to do more work to receive rights, later awards will mean that ownership races
may last longer and involve a greater number of participants and greater levels
of wasteful duplication of effort.
59
The other, and related, problem with late
awards concerns their incentive effects. Because those who unsuccessfully
compete for a resource get nothing for their troubles, would-be competitors may
be discouraged from entering the competition in the first place.
60
The greater
their troubles—i.e., the larger the investment in time, labor, and money they
must make to obtain the resource—the greater the discouragement.
61
Given the wasteful duplication problem, this could be a good thing, up to a
point: fear of losing might reduce the number of competitors and therefore the
amount of wasted investment.
62
But it would be the rare case that these two
factors would be perfectly offsetting.
In many cases, late awards will not have these two offsetting effects on entry
simultaneously, as the two often arise in different settings. Excessive entry that
leads to wasteful, duplicative effort and rent dissipation is likely to arise in
settings where participants are reasonably assured that the per-participant
expected value of joining the race are greater than or equal to the cost of
participating.
63
Good examples are the fishery,
64
a grazing commons, and
for granting property rights early can avoid wasteful duplications of effort); Aditya Bamzai,
Comment, The Wasteful Duplication Thesis in Natural Monopoly Regulation, 71 U.
CHI. L.
REV. 1525, 1525 (2004).
59
Peter S. Menell & Suzanne Scotchmer, Intellectual Property Law, in 2 HANDBOOK OF
LAW AND ECONOMICS 1475, 1489 (A.M. Polinsky & S. Shavell eds., 2007).
60
Steve P. Calandrillo, An Economic Analysis of Property Rights in Information:
Justifications and Problems of Exclusive Rights, Incentives to Generate Information, and the
Alternative of a Government-Run Reward System, 9 FORDHAM INTELL. PROP. MEDIA & ENT.
L.J. 301, 307 n.17 (1998) (“However, we must not lose sight of the wasted effort put forth by
the loser of the race, which is a social loss that is usually unrecoverable. The reward system
would not solve this dilemma, but the existence of the problem militates towards a scheme in
which the beneficiary of the reward should be recognized early on . . . .”).
61
This concern extends more broadly than the concern about wasteful duplication of effort.
If a competitor is able to capitalize on a would-be claimant’s contributions, there is no social
waste as such, but there is a private loss when the claimant is unable to recoup her costs. The
disincentive to participation this creates can thus result in what is ultimately a social loss.
62
Cf. Lueck, supra note 32, at 399-400 (suggesting heterogeneity among claimants may
reduce wasteful competition by discouraging entry).
63
Richard S. Higgins, William F. Shughart II & Robert G. Tollison, Free Entry and
Efficient Rent Seeking: Efficient Rents 2, 46 P
UB. CHOICE 247, 255 (1985) (“[W]hen there are
no restrictions on the number of individuals who may vie for the right to capture . . . entry
will occur, and resources will be spent up to the point where the expected net value of the
transfer is zero.”).
64
For a classical treatment of one such case, see H. Scott Gordon, The Economic Theory
of Common-Property Resource: The Fishery, 62 J.
POL. ECON. 124, 130-31 (1954)
410 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
multiple-party drilling into a common oil reservoir. To illustrate, imagine an
open fishery governed by the rule of capture. Assume that the per-day costs and
benefits, as a function of the number of fishermen, are as follows:
Table 1. The Fishery: Public and Private Costs and Yield as a Function of the
Number of Fishermen (in Dollars).
Fishermen Total
Cost
Total
Expected
Yield
Net Expected
Social Value
Net Expected Profit
per Fisherman
0 0 0 0 0
1 10 16 6 6
2 20 29 9 4.5
3 30 40 10 3.33
4 40 49 9 2.25
5 50 56 6 1.2
6 60 61 1 0.16
7 70 64 (-6) (-0.85)
The first column in Table 1 simply designates different numbers of fishermen
that may operate on the fishery. The second column reflects the assumption that
operating a boat on the fishery costs ten dollars, such that the total social cost of
fishing is ten times the number of fishermen. The third column reflects an
assumption of diminishing marginal returns per unit of effort, a general
phenomenon observed in the world. Here, this assumption can be motivated by
the realization that fishery congestion reduces the fishery’s yield.
65
The fourth
column is simply the difference between the third and the second columns. The
last column divides the fourth column by the first to obtain the per fisherman net
expected return.
As Table 1 suggests, it would be socially optimal that only three fishermen
operate on the fishery, which would maximize the fourth column, “Net Expected
Social Value.” However, since all are free to join the fishing race, as many as
six fishermen would enter, because the expected private return to entry would
still be positive (see the last column). Though such entry would be privately
beneficial, it is excessive from a social point of view because it decreases the net
social value of the fishery. Each of the fourth, fifth, and sixth entrants increases
(suggesting that, on common properties with free entry, number of entrants would be
excessive, tending to dissipate value of the resource). A similar scenario applies for an oil
field that lies beneath land parcels owned by many owners, from which each could drill and
extract oil.
65
The diminishing returns assumption can be motivated easily respecting the fishery.
Doubling the number of boats on the fishery from one to two, say, will not likely result in
double yield because of friction between the two fishermen: sometimes one would catch a
fish that the other would have caught had it been alone on the fishery, or because they would
get in each other’s way occasionally and slow down.
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 411
social costs by ten dollars, but increases social value by an amount lesser than
ten. In essence, each fisherman joining the fishery disregards the negative
externality it imposes on others. For our purposes, an implicit assumption
supports the conclusion of excessive entry, which is that fish are many, that a
fishing day involves the fishing of many fish, and that all fishermen are similarly
situated and can observe the number of fishermen on the fishery. In such cases,
each fishermen knows, virtually with certainty, that she will cover her costs and
will not operate at a loss.
Things are different in a scenario where race participants are not assured of
recouping their participation costs with reasonable certainty. Such is
characteristically the case when there is one prize, allocated to one winner at the
end of a relatively costly and prolonged pursuit. Take, for instance, a potential
company pursuing a pharmaceutical patent where the expected revenue—if the
chase is successful—is $1.5 billion, but where research and development
(“R&D”) is expected to last five years and cost $1 billion. Patents are awarded
under a rule of capture to the first to complete R&D. Firms cannot know how
many others are participating in the R&D race. If firms believe that there’s a
significant chance that a rival might get the patent before they do, the firms may
be reluctant to begin R&D, fearing a worst case scenario where they may invest
nearly the full one billion dollars only to discover that a rival filed for a patent
before they did. In contrast to the first scenario, a participant in this race cannot
be assured to cover costs (i.e., there is a greater risk involved), and does not
know exactly how many others are already in the race (so she might join a race
with a negative expected value).
Later awards may further deter entry in cases where a claimant can free-ride
on the investments of others who have accomplished earlier steps that enable
capture.
66
While free-riding avoids duplication of effort, it can lead to especially
sharp disincentive effects to the extent it weakens the correspondence between
the size of investment and the likelihood of winning the competition.
67
If
ownership is assigned to someone who merely delivers the coup de grâce, others
will be reluctant to undertake costlier or more difficult parts of the hunt that
make the ultimate kill possible.
The downward sloping curve in Figure 1 represents the marginal benefit of
delaying the moment that the law regards as possession in the chronology of a
resource’s pursuit. The curve is positive, indicating that there is always some
benefit to delaying the award of rights. The further along in the chronology of
the chase the pursuer is, the greater the probability that she will complete it
66
See, e.g., Lemley, supra note 30, at 1039-40 (“The professed fear is that property owners
won’t invest sufficient resources in their property if others can free ride on that investment.”).
67
Jerome H. Reichman, How Trade Secrecy Law Generates a Natural Semicommons of
Innovative Know-How, in T
HE LAW AND THEORY OF TRADE SECRECY: A HANDBOOK OF
CONTEMPORARY RESEARCH 185, 196 (Rochell C. Dreyfuss, Katherine J. Strandburg & Edward
Elgar eds., 2011) (noting that free riding by competitors creates disincentives to invest in
innovation in the first place).
412 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
successfully. Gains represented by increases in the probability of success often
accrue at a decreasing rate, however.
To illustrate, imagine a hunter chasing a fox in a dense forest. Assume that
the hunter is moving at twenty feet per second and the fox at ten feet per second,
and that the probability that the hunter will catch the fox is a decreasing linear
function of the area that the hunter needs to scout in search of the fox. If the
hunter spots the fox from one hundred feet away, by the time she reaches the
place she saw it, the fox could be hiding anywhere in a circle with an area of
roughly 2,500ߨ square feet (ߨ*50
2
), because the fox could have traveled fifty
feet in any direction during that time. By the same logic, if the sighting were
from eighty feet away, the fox would have to be searched for in an area of 1,600ߨ
square feet, and if it were seen from sixty feet away, the search area would be
900ߨ square feet. The first twenty foot movement reduced the search area by
900ߨ square feet (from 2,500ߨ to 1,600ߨ), the next twenty foot movement
toward the fox reduced that area by only 700ߨ square feet (from 1,600ߨ to
900ߨ). So while the benefits of progressing in the race toward the fox remain
positive, they accrue at a decreasing rate.
The upward sloping curve in Figure 1, meanwhile, represents the marginal
cost of delaying the moment defined as possession. Again, this curve is positive
because there is a cost to prolonging the race—racers will incur duplicative and
wasteful costs throughout the relevant timeframe. It is drawn as upward sloping
because longer races may be more costly per unit of time: longer hunting races,
for example, generally require the participants to carry more equipment and
provisions. Moreover, races that last longer may allow more parties to join. The
likelihood of either wasteful duplication of effort or depressed participation
resulting in underdevelopment can therefore be expected to increase with time.
68
A few further comments about the relationship between time and resource
waste are in order. The literature on possession has given considerable attention
to issues of wasteful competition associated with possession-based regimes,
with a special emphasis on timing issues.
69
Any rule for claiming resources has
68
While Figure 1 depicts what we believe are the most likely shapes of the marginal cost
and benefit curves associated with ownership races, these shapes are not essential. For
example, our analysis applies equally well to races characterized by a fixed marginal cost. In
that case, the marginal cost curve would be flat, and nothing in the analysis would change
materially. The optimal time of possession would still be determined by the intersection of
the two curves, and a relatively high fixed marginal cost would suggest that possession should
be awarded earlier in time during the race compared to an alternative of a lower fixed marginal
cost. See supra note 50.
69
See, e.g., Anderson & Hill, supra note 57, at 177 (“Economics literature on the evolution
of property rights has increasingly emphasized the optimal timing for establishing those
rights.”); Richard A. Epstein, Past and Future: The Temporal Dimension of the Law of
Property, 64 W
ASH. U. L.Q. 667, 670 (1986) (“Time offers a unique measuring rod, sufficient
in principle to resolve two or two thousand competing claims for priority.”); David D.
Haddock, First Possession Versus Optimal Timing: Limiting the Dissipation of Economic
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 413
the potential to distort people’s behavior because in theory, a rational claimant
should be willing to spend up to the expected value of a given resource itself in
order to obtain it.
70
Unless there is social value in the actions that the law requires
a person to take to establish a claim to a resource that is at least equal to the
value of the resource to a claimant, the rule will lead to excessive claiming and
deadweight loss (including the value of establishing ownership). It might not be
the end of the world to have to queue up the night before to get tickets to a rock
concert, for example, but on the whole, the queuing process itself wastes
people’s time and is justifiable only if there is no better way to distribute tickets.
In this last case, an auction rather than a first possession based queue might be
the better allocation mechanism.
71
Early awards under a first-committed-searcher rule present a special problem
in this regard. The genius of anchoring the award of rights in possession is that
they can avoid the sort of waste that a claiming protocol might otherwise
generate because they require claimants to perform a task that is itself necessary
for the resource to be used. A rule awarding ownership of a parcel of farmland
to the best dressed person at City Hall next Tuesday creates incentives to engage
in otherwise pointless behavior—showing up at City Hall in fancy clothes on
Tuesday. By contrast, a rule awarding ownership of the land to the person who
begins the process of cultivating it only encourages a claimant to do something
she would have done anyway to enjoy the property. It is effectively costless.
72
This singular advantage of reliance on possession is less likely to hold true,
however, to the extent possession rules adhere to a first-committed-searcher
model. Since first-committed searcher-rules identify steps that are more
preliminary in the overall process of putting a resource to use, there is a greater
risk that those steps are not actually optimal, or even necessary, to the resource’s
ultimate development.
73
So, for example, one problem with awarding possession
Value, 64 WASH. U. L.Q. 775, 783 (1986) (“Timing is also a concern when modeling
innovation and the sometimes valuable patents and copyrights that follow.”); Lueck, supra
note 32, at 398 (“Maximizing resource value is, in effect, a problem of optimally timing the
establishment of rights . . . .”); Ronen Perry & Tal Z. Zarsky, Queues in Law, 99 I
OWA L. REV.
1595, 1629 (2014) (suggesting that allocation of “specific assets at a relatively early stage,
when claimant heterogeneity is still large” can partly resolve issue of wasteful races and
duplicative investments).
70
The value of the resource would be discounted by the probability of being unsuccessful
in claiming it.
71
See supra note 50.
72
There may be costs and distortions, however, to the extent the action constituting
possession does not facilitate a particular use, or worse, is actually incompatible with that use.
Animal conservation, for instance, is at odds with a rule requiring mortal wounding, and an
interest in confidentiality of an expressive work would conflict with a rule requiring
publication.
73
See Claeys, supra note 53, at 10 (noting that early award of property rights can lead to
underutilization of resources).
414 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
of the fox in Pierson v. Post to the first person to saddle up and mount a horse
is that it might not actually be necessary to use a horse to catch the fox—as
farmer Pierson showed.
Even when possession rules are perfectly designed, there is still the potential
for distortion, however, insofar as they center on first possession and therefore
reward not just the ability to take possession but to do so faster than anyone else.
Awarding a pot of gold to the first person across the finish line creates identical
incentives to invest in training, whether the race itself is a one-hundred-meter
sprint or a marathon. The sprinter will train just as hard as the marathoner to win
the race, even though the amount of energy needed to move a human body 26.2
miles is much greater than the amount needed to move it one hundred meters.
And unlike possession itself, faster possession is not necessarily essential to the
optimal use of the resource.
74
For this reason, first-committed-searcher rules
may have some value to the extent they do not require as much work to be
completed before ownership is awarded. How much this is true is uncertain,
however. If instead of doing more to develop a resource, claimants direct their
energies to qualify as first-committed searchers faster, early awards may face
the same problem of inefficient racing for resources.
75
In addition, faster
claiming and faster resource development may often be valuable in and of itself
and also generate positive external benefits—particularly for intellectual
property.
76
Concerns about wasteful racing may therefore be less pressing than
they are sometimes made out to be.
77
It should also be noted that, apart from
investments in speed, competition can generate social waste by encouraging
behavior intended to tilt the competitive field—theft and fencing, espionage and
secrecy, sabotage and conflict.
78
To the extent later awards translate to more
protracted competition, they present a greater danger of social cost through such
anti-competitive conduct.
Figure 2 sets out the central concerns in the design of rules for awarding
property rights. The costs identified are relative: in most cases, the drawbacks
that are listed can occur at some level with either late or early awards, but they
74
See Lueck, supra note 32, at 399 (noting that “rush” of competitors can lead to early
grant of possession that is neither socially optimal nor valuable).
75
See Donald G. McFetridge & Douglas A. Smith, Patents, Prospects, and Economic
Surplus: A Comment, 23 J.L. & ECON. 197, 201 (1980) (noting negative effects when
possession rights go to “first rather than the best” claimant).
76
See Douglas W. Allen, Homesteading and Property Rights; or, “How the West Was
Really Won, 34 J.L.
& ECON. 1, 1-6 (1991) (arguing that incentives for faster settlement
created by 19th century homesteading policies reduced enforcement costs and helped secure
U.S. government claims to western land).
77
See Duffy, supra note 15, at 467-68 (noting that inefficiencies of racing in intellectual
property are not significant).
78
See ROBERT D. ATKINSON & STEPHEN J. EZELL, INNOVATION ECONOMICS: THE RACE FOR
GLOBAL ADVANTAGE 190 (2012) (“[T]he race for global innovation advantage creates both
global opportunities and threats, because countries can implement their innovation policies in
ways that are either ‘good,’ ‘bad,’ or ‘ugly.’”).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 415
are thought to be comparatively more serious with one model than with the other.
At least within the context of intellectual property, failure to follow through is
generally the most significant danger associated with early awards—especially
where early awards result in rights that are broader than anything the claimant
could possibly develop—while disincentives to compete and wasteful
duplication are generally the most significant drawback of late ones.
Figure 2. Early vs. Late Awards.
Costs of Early Awards
(First Committed Searcher)
Costs of Late Awards
(Actual Capture)
Deadweight loss from misallocation to
less capable/incapable claimants
Resource underuse/non-use
Transaction and reassignment costs
Wasteful claiming conduct
Inefficient racing to begin search
Unnecessary search behavior
Slower capture/completion
(when faster development desired)
Greater uncertainty as to resource
boundaries and characteristics
Often an ambiguous standard that
requires discretion in application (e.g.,
as to what “committed” means)
Disincentives to compete from risk of
lost investment, especially with free-
riding
Wasteful duplication of effort
Wasteful claiming conduct
Inefficient racing to capture
Inefficient capture rates
(e.g., endangered species)
Where rights are time-limited, longer
effective exclusivity period
Other competitive waste
Self-help, fencing, secrecy
Theft and espionage
Interfering capture activities
Sabotage, conflict, violence
The basic trade-off discussed above and depicted in Figures 1 and 2 has been
idealized and simplified in our discussion so far. In practice, administrability
concerns are a third variable that is often critical.
79
In Figure 1, the proper point
in time to award property rights would in theory be time t*the exact point in
the possession continuum where the marginal benefit of delay just equals its
cost. For a number of reasons, however, the meaning of possession in various
contexts will also be shaped by practical demands like the need for clear rules,
intuitive concepts, and notice to race participants. To avoid wasteful duplication
of effort and lost investments, for instance, it is important for would-be
79
Michael W. Carroll, One Size Does Not Fit All: A Framework for Tailoring Intellectual
Property Rights, 70
OHIO ST. L.J. 1363, 1424-30 (2009) (discussing importance of
administrability when creating effective IP regime).
416 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
competitors to be able to observe and understand what counts as possession
fairly easily so that, e.g., they know not to continue expending efforts to win a
race that has already ended.
80
It does not do much good to end the race early
(i.e., declare a winner and stop the simultaneous search effort) if the other
participants do not know it is over. A clear test for possession also helps forestall
conflict among would-be competitors, encourages investment and facilitates
exchange by providing security of holdings, and reduces the costs of
administering and policing a property system.
81
While the need for clear and
intuitive tests for possession does not intrinsically align with either early or late
awards, in practice it tended to skew in favor of later awards at common law
because actual capture is often, though not always, more unambiguous than a
committed search.
The technology of the hunt determines what points in its chronology can even
be considered as viable candidates for possession from the perspective of
providing notice. In the context of hunting foxes, for example, it seems that such
informational considerations push for the rule of capture. What earlier stage in
the hunt could be set as the standard for a first-committed searcher? A certain
distance from the fox? A wound? If so, what type of wound confers property
rights (a scratch or mortal wounds)? What are the chances that other hunters
would be able to see both the hunter and the fox and determine the distance
between them in a dense forest? In the context of whaling, by contrast, the act
of sinking a harpoon into the body of the whale in the open sea by a party in hot
pursuit is a clear—or at least much clearer—informational marker to third
parties, and makes the first-committed-searcher rule a much more viable
candidate. The administrability concern adds to those discussed previously, and
can push the timing of grants of exclusive rights to either earlier or later points
in time.
To return to the example of Ellickson’s whalers cited earlier,
82
the trade-offs
embodied in the choice between first-committed-searcher and actual capture
models are evident in both the features that were universal among whaling norms
across all whaling fisheries and the ways in which those norms differed. As
Ellickson notes, no group of whalers adopted a rule awarding exclusive rights in
a whale to the first crew to lower a boat in pursuit.
83
That would be too soon.
Why? It would create too great a risk of awarding the prize to someone less
80
Cf. Kitch, supra note 27, at 278 (arguing that patents act as signaling devices to
competing firms to reduce amount of duplicative investment in innovation).
81
Joseph William Singer, The Rule of Reason in Property Law, 46 U.C. DAVIS L. REV.
1369, 1376 (2013) (noting that clear property regime “allows actors to invest in reliance on
clear rules of the game, avoids unfair surprise, controls the arbitrary discretion of judges, and
promotes equality before the law by treating like cases alike”).
82
See supra notes 45-49 and accompanying text (discussing Robert Ellickson’s seminal
study of nineteenth century whalers).
83
See Ellickson, supra note 45, at 88 n.14, 95 (noting that certain norms, including “first
boat in the water” were not observed in whaling industry).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 417
capable of completing the task of capture, it would create incentives to get boats
in the water earlier than would be optimal, and it would not send a clear signal
as to which whale the whaler intended to pursue. At the other end of the
spectrum, neither did any of the whaling communities wait until a whale was
actually killed to assign claims to the animal. Among other difficulties, such a
rule would risk rewarding free-riders seeking to benefit from the significant
efforts others had already made to subdue a whale. Rather, both rules—iron-
holds-the-whale (first-committed searcher) and fast-fish-loose-fish (rule of
capture)—pick points that are in between.
The same concerns also help account for the way norms among whalers
differed in different contexts. Sperm whales tend to be relatively fast swimmers
and vigorous fighters,
84
prone to diving when harpooned, which often made it
necessary for the fishermen to cut the line lest their ship sink. Their hunt
involved costly and prolonged chases—over days—during which the whale
would be tired out. Waiting until a sperm whale had been brought under actual
control before giving a whaler a claim to the animal risked failing to reward
those whose early efforts made later capture possible—the free-riding problem.
The iron-holds-the-whale rule therefore seems to have been adapted to
conditions presented in sperm whale fisheries.
85
The right whales predominant
elsewhere, by contrast, were comparatively slow swimmers with docile
temperaments.
86
There was little need to award possession sooner, and waiting
until the whale had been brought under actual control ensured that the whale
went to the person who had “performed the hardest part of the hunt.”
87
To summarize: the primary problem with early awards is the risk that a
claimant will fail to proceed successfully with development of a resource after
being awarded it. The primary problems with late awards are the potential for
prolonging costly multiparty races and disincentivizing race participation when
participation is time-consuming and costly. Determining the moment of
possession should be made in light of the ability to convey clear notice to race
participants as to the moment in which a resource is taken into possession. Those
considerations play out differently for different resources.
II. O
RIGINAL ACQUISITION IN INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
The concept of possession might not seem like it has much to do with
intellectual property. Possession has a certain physical flavor,
88
and the
resources IP law governs are intangible by definition. A human being cannot
84
See id. at 425 (discussing nature of sperm whales).
85
See id.
86
Id.
87
Id. at 89.
88
See OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES, JR., THE COMMON LAW 216 (Little, Brown & Co. 1945)
(1881) (“To gain possession, then, a man must stand in a certain physical relation to the object
and to the rest of the world . . . .”).
418 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
literally reach out and grab an idea, much less skewer it with a harpoon. As one
venerable eighteenth-century jurist put it, “But how is possession to be taken, or
any act of occupancy to be asserted, on mere intellectual ideas? . . . All writers
agree that no act of occupancy can be asserted on a bare idea of the mind.”
89
Yet the concept of possession can be extended to apply to intellectual
creations without conceptual or linguistic violence. We certainly speak of
possessing intangibles, like a sense of humor
90
or a secret.
91
Indeed, IP doctrines
occasionally invoke the concept of possession explicitly, most obviously in the
case of patent law’s “written description” requirement.
92
Just like “property”
serves as an imperfect analogy to “intellectual property,” so does “first
possession” to “original acquisition of intellectual property.”
The concept of possession, as property law has traditionally conceived it, is
oriented around the notion of control, a state of affairs that brings a person
substantially closer to being able to put a resource to use.
93
Although the various
doctrines governing the award of IP rights for the most part avoid the language
of possession, the basic concept of possession carries over to intellectual
property and the model of first possession developed in property law can be
usefully extended to major segments of IP law. This Articles stresses that there
is no single first possession doctrine in these fields. Multiple interacting
doctrines and concepts that together function as a system of original acquisition
govern the award of rights.
94
89
Millar v. Taylor (1769) 98 Eng. Rep. 201, 231 (KB) (Yates, J., dissenting).; see also
Wheaton v. Peters, 33 U.S. (8 Pet.) 591, 669 (1834) (Thompson, J., dissenting) (discussing
Justice Yate’s dissent in Millar).
90
See, e.g., David E. Engdahl, John Marshall’s “Jeffersonian” Concept of Judicial
Review, 42 DUKE L.J. 279, 329 (1992) (stating that Chief Justice John Marshall “possessed a
self-effacing charm and good humor”).
91
See, e.g., ELIZABETH A. ROWE & SHARON K. SANDEEN, CASES AND MATERIALS ON
TRADE SECRET LAW 14-17 (2012) (noting that for over a century and a half since founding,
trade secrecy law in the United States developed primarily through common law
adjudication).
92
A patent specification must “demonstrate that the patentee was in possession of the
invention that is claimed.” Capon v. Eshhar, 418 F.3d 1349, 1357 (Fed. Cir. 2005). Further, a
patent filing must “put the public in possession of what the party claims as his own invention.”
Univ. of Rochester v. G.D. Searle & Co., 358 F.3d 916, 924 (Fed. Cir. 2004) (quoting Evans
v. Eaton, 20 U.S. (7 Wheat.) 356, 433-34 (1822)). If a prior disclosure of the invention was
sufficient to place the invention “in the possession of the public,” however, no patent can
issue. Eli Lilly & Co. v. Zenith Goldline Pharm., Inc., 471 F.3d 1369, 1375 (Fed. Cir. 2006).
93
See Pierson v. Post, 3 Cai. 175, 178 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1805) (requiring acts that bring
animal within person’s “certain control” before that person can be said to be in possession of
it).
94
Indeed, patent law’s written description requirement, which refers to possession by
name, plays a relatively peripheral role in the larger set of issues we are concerned with and
is not a major focus of this Article’s analysis.
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 419
Conceptually speaking, first possession has several basic hallmarks. It is, of
course, a device that establishes when property rights begin and the identity of
the first person to hold them.
95
It is, moreover, a relatively decentralized
mechanism for doing so: initial ownership depends on the performance of some
sort of act by the first owner that, in principle, does not require any direct
involvement with a governmental authority.
96
Perfection of rights can be made
contingent on registration with or verification by some government body that
the requisite action has been performed—i.e., that the claimant has taken
possession—but the act of taking possession is itself undertaken by private
actors at their own initiative.
97
In terms of its more specific content, first possession is a system based on
temporal priority—the first person to do something wins. Others who carry out
the necessary steps are precluded if someone else did so before them. As for the
possession element, it entails more than mere desire or plotting and less than
ultimate consumption, or even the completion of every task necessary for
consumption to occur.
98
Possession is oriented around the notion of practical
control, in which the would-be owner stands in a special relationship to the
resource and changes its character in a manner consistent with its eventual use
and consumption.
99
In what follows, this Article reviews a number of patent,
trademark, and copyright doctrines which together align with this set of features.
Original acquisition rules play two related yet analytically distinct roles. First,
these rules determine winners and losers in priority disputes among competitors
who are racing simultaneously to own the same resource.
100
This may be thought
of as the “first” part of “first possession.” While this context generally parallels
the discussion of common law priority contests featured prominently in Pierson
v. Post, intellectual property brings its own quirks.
Second, original acquisition rules also determine the point in time—and
equivalently the standard of performance—at which entitlements vest,
95
See, e.g., Lueck, supra note 32, at 425 (describing how first possession-based whaling
customs made it clear who had valid claim to whale and when).
96
Rose, supra note 5, at 76 (“Possession thus means a clear act, whereby all the world
understands that the pursuer has ‘an unequivocal intention of appropriating the [property] to
his individual use.’” (quoting Pierson, 3 Cai. at 178)).
97
John L. McCormack, Torrens and Recording: Land Title Assurance in the Computer
Age, 18 WM. MITCHELL L. REV. 61, 67 (1992) (noting that recording land deed with the
government is way to perfect ownership, but is not required to have valid legal claim to
property).
98
Detroit Edison Co. v. Mich. Air Pollution Control Comm’n, 423 N.W.2d 306, 310
(Mich. Ct. App. 1998) (“To constitute a protectable right, a person must have more than an
abstract need, desire or unilateral expectation of the right.”).
99
Nicole L. Johnson, Property Without Possession, 24 YALE J. ON REG. 205, 223 (2007)
(noting that right to surface water, for instance, is partly determined by the extent the owner
puts resource to “beneficial use”).
100
See, e.g., Pierson, 3 Cai. at 175.
420 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
irrespective of the existence of a priority contest.
101
This may be thought of as
the “possession” part of “first possession.” This can often take the form of a
determination about what it is that can be possessed and become the subject of
property rights. This function is more pronounced in intellectual property: while
the nature of a fox is unchanged whether it is owned under either a first-
committed-searcher rule or a rule of capture, in intellectual property, the thing
owned often differs with the rule of original acquisition. Since the would-be
owner often creates and perfects the thing to be owned, a later time of acquisition
practically means that intellectual creations (or ideas) at an earlier stage of
development are not subject to ownership. This function of original acquisition
rules implicates questions about both the acquisition of any rights whatsoever as
well as the scope of protection in cases where some rights have clearly been
acquired.
These two functions are intimately connected. Whether a claimant has
performed the action necessary to acquire exclusive rights will very frequently
dispose of any priority questions. The two issues can be disaggregated, however,
and the discussion that follows examines them separately, at least in part.
Questions of what might be thought of as pure priority, involving conflicting
claims by multiple actors for the very same resource are discussed under the
heading of “priority.” Questions that center more squarely on the standard for
protection itself are discussed in terms of “protectability.” The partial separation
in the analysis grows out of a recognition that protectability questions are more
pronounced for intellectual property than for physical resources. Nevertheless,
it should be remembered that there is a great deal of overlap between the two
aspects of claiming by possession and the division should be understood only as
differences in emphasis and not as establishing mutually exclusive categories of
doctrine.
A. Patent
Priority. The process of invention can be broken down into a series of mental
and physical steps beginning with conception of the core inventive idea—what
is often imagined as the “Eureka!” moment
102
—and ending with what patent
lawyers call “reduction to practice,” which can be accomplished by assembling
a working version of the invention or by filing a valid patent application that
101
See, e.g., Lueck, supra note 32, at 425 (describing customary standards of performance
required to establish valid claim to whale); see also supra notes 45-49 and accompanying text
(discussing Ellickson’s seminal study of nineteenth century whalers).
102
Or perhaps, “hmm, that’s funny . . . .” See CRAIG C. LUNDBERG & CHERI A. YOUNG,
FOUNDATIONS FOR INQUIRY: CHOICES AND TRADE-OFFS IN THE ORGANIZATIONAL SCIENCES
378 (2005); J
ESSICA SILBEY, THE EUREKA MYTH: CREATORS, INNOVATORS, AND EVERYDAY
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY 25-26 (2015) (discussing role of “Eureka” moment in process of
innovation and law’s treatment of “Eureka” moment).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 421
teaches others how to do so.
103
For our purposes, the process is analogous to the
hunt of wild animals like foxes and whales, which similarly goes through stages
of inspiration, pursuit, capture, and use.
104
Patent law decides between rival
claimants to inventive technologies by identifying the first person to reach a
certain stage on this developmental timeline, and in this way it can be mapped
onto the general model of first possession that describes common law property.
Even more so than with tangible goods, reliance upon first possession in the IP
context raises questions about how to model possession.
The two basic approaches to first possession we have discussed—first-
committed searcher and actual capture—produce the same result when the same
actor is first to both begin and complete the hunt. But often this does not occur,
and when it does not, the two rules come apart. Suppose, for example, that
Edison has an idea for a particular invention before Tesla, a lightbulb let’s say.
But Tesla is nevertheless the first to complete the intellectual hunt, building an
actual working version of the idea. In the language of patent law, Edison was the
first to conceive the invention but Tesla was the first to reduce it to practice.
Such a fact pattern is depicted in the timeline in Figure 3.
Figure 3. Priority Disputes.
Edison
conceives
Tesla
conceives
Tesla reduces
to practice
Edison reduces
to practice
In U.S. patent law from the start of the republic and for more than two
centuries thereafter, this sort of invention race was governed by what was in
effect a first-committed-searcher rule. Even today, for patent applications filed
103
See Hybritech, Inc. v. Monoclonal Antibodies, Inc., 802 F.2d 1367, 1376 (Fed. Cir.
1986) (requiring inventor to reduce conception to practice, which “requires that the claimed
invention work for its intended purpose”); Brunswick Corp. v. United States, 34 Fed. Cl. 532,
583-84 (1995) (noting importance of timing of reducing conception to practice).
104
Conception requires more than simply a general idea of how to proceed. See Burroughs
Wellcome Co. v. Barr Labs., Inc., 40 F.3d 1223, 1228 (Fed. Cir. 1994) (“Conception is
complete only when the idea is so clearly defined in the inventor’s mind that only ordinary
skill would be necessary to reduce the invention to practice, without extensive research or
experimentation.”).
422 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
before March 16, 2013,
105
the patent would be awarded to whomever was first
to conceive of the invention provided that party exercised “reasonable diligence”
in reducing the invention to practice.
106
Under this regime, Edison would receive
the patent, so long as he remained in diligent pursuit of the ultimate working
invention. Such priority disputes were adjudicated through quasi-judicial
“interference proceedings” before the Board of Patent Appeals and
Interferences. This so-called first-to-invent priority rule is a clear patent law
analog to the first-committed-searcher model of first possession.
The first-to-invent rule was abandoned following enactment of the Leahy-
Smith America Invents Act (“AIA”) in 2011, the most comprehensive overhaul
of U.S. patent law in at least half a century.
107
Its most prominent change was to
replace the first-to-invent rule with a first-to-file system, or more precisely, a
system that awards patents to the first person to disclose their invention to the
public, whether by filing a patent application or through other public acts.
108
The
AIA thus pushes back the temporal lynchpin from the beginning of the inventive
process to its end.
109
The upshot of this new rule is that even if someone sets out in pursuit of an
invention before the competition and is thus the first committed inventor, the
race goes on and may very well be won by another who manages to complete
the process first. Under the AIA, the patent in the situation described in Figure
105
See Leahy-Smith America Invents Act, Pub. L. No. 112-29, § 146(1)(n), 125 Stat. 284,
293 (2011) (codified as amended in scattered sections of 35 U.S.C.).
106
See 35 U.S.C. § 102(g) (2012), (supplanted by Leahy-Smith America Invents Act in
2011); Griffith v. Kanamaru, 816 F.2d 624, 625-29 (Fed. Cir. 1987) (applying first to invent
priority rules).
107
Pub. L. No. 112-29, 125 Stat. 284 (2011) (codified as amended in scattered sections of
35 U.S.C.); Joe Matal, A Guide to the Legislative History of the America Invents Act: Part I
of II, 21 FED. CIR. B.J. 435, 435 (2012) (stating that the AIA “arguably makes the most
substantial changes to the law since those imposed by the Patent Act of 1836”).
108
Still more precisely, the AIA awards patents to the first to invent and then either file or
publicly disclose, whether by written description, commercial sale, or acts otherwise making
the technology available to the public. See 35 U.S.C. § 102 (stating that patent exists if
invention is “patented, described in a printed publication, or in public use, on sale, or
otherwise available to the public”). While forms of public disclosure other than filing can be
used to establish priority, filing an application and the issuance of a patent by the U.S. Patent
and Trademark Office (“USPTO”) is still required for any patent rights to be awarded.
109
Technically, exclusive rights vest upon the filing of a valid patent application
(considered “constructive reduction to practice”). See
U.S. DEPT OF COMMERCE, U.S. PATENT
& TRADEMARK OFFICE, MANUAL OF PATENT EXAMINING PROCEDURE § 2138.05(I) (2014).
Alternatively, rights vest upon the publishing of an “enabling” disclosure, followed by timely
filing within twelve months; an enabling disclosure is one that allows those skilled in the
relevant art to make the invention without “undue experimentation.” See id. § 2164. On the
relationship between invention-based rights and filing, see Adam Mossoff, Who Cares What
Thomas Jefferson Thought About Patents? Reevaluating the Patent “Privilege” in Historical
Context, 92 C
ORNELL L. REV. 953, 995-97 (2007).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 423
3 would now go to Tesla rather than Edison because Tesla was the first to file a
valid application.
110
The AIA, in other words, can be seen as moving the U.S.
patent system from a first-committed-searcher model to one representing a rule
of capture.
Protectability. The possessory timeline also speaks to the nature of what can
be patented at all, even in the absence of a priority dispute. At a very basic level,
the answer is that a patent must be issued by the U.S. Patent and Trademark
Office (“USPTO”)—something that was true even before the AIA was
enacted—and this in turn requires actual or constructive reduction to practice.
But the choice described above between a first committed inventor and an actual
capture approach can be illuminated further by situating it within a still-broader
chronology. That chronology begins with the discovery of basic scientific truths,
mathematical axioms, and other abstract principles; it proceeds through applied
research either to find real-world uses for such knowledge or to apply such
knowledge to solve known problems; it continues to the actual invention of a
device or process having some practical and beneficial use; from there it
proceeds to the perfection of the invention to generate a commercially desirable
product; from there to production and marketing; and then it concludes with the
sale or use of the invention and the enjoyment of whatever benefits it provides.
Both the pre- and post-AIA regimes allow inventors to receive exclusive rights
at points some distance removed from either end of that larger timeline.
111
One of the fundamental preconditions to patentability under U.S. patent law
is that an invention be “useful,” a principle known as the utility requirement.
112
Patent law could adopt a rule allowing the award of exclusive rights as soon as
a person comes to grasp a general principle that is likely to lead to one or more
practical applications. It is hardly a stretch of the English language to say that,
for instance, the idea of producing light by passing an electric current through a
material with a moderately high level of electrical resistance is in some sense a
“useful” one. Alternatively, patent law could condition the award of exclusive
rights on actual commercial exploitation through the sale of a working product
based on that information. On this view, an invention simply is not useful until
it is actually put to real-world use of demonstrated value. Patent law adopts
neither of these positions. Instead, it follows something of a middle course,
110
Filing a complete and enabling application with the USPTO qualifies as constructive
reduction to practice. See 35 U.S.C. § 100(i).
111
In addition to the priority rules described here, the time bar in patent law makes
patentability depend on filing for patent protection relatively early, even if there is no danger
of being beaten by a competitor. See id. § 202(g).
112
See U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 8 (empowering Congress “[t]o promote the Progress of
Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive
Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries” (emphasis added)); 35 U.S.C. § 101
(stating that patent may be granted to one who invents something “new and useful”).
424 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
requiring that a patent applicant demonstrate a non-speculative practical
application for the invention.
113
This is a relatively minimal showing and makes it possible to receive a patent
at a fairly preliminary stage, when more needs to be done before the patentee
can benefit from the patent.
114
Claimants do not need to show that an invention
is commercially feasible or genuinely valuable,
115
and often decades—
sometimes even centuries—pass before patents are commercialized in
markets.
116
Nor must a claimant obtain regulatory approvals necessary to make
or sell an invention—a crucial consideration with pharmaceuticals.
117
Nothing
more is required to receive a patent, even under the AIA, once invention has
occurred and been disclosed.
That said, the patent system as a whole does have features that push awards
further down the developmental timeline, a number of which have become more
113
See ROBERT P. MERGES, PETER S. MENELL & MARK A. LEMLEY, INTELLECTUAL
PROPERTY IN THE NEW TECHNOLOGICAL AGE 186 (6th ed. 2012) (explaining that invention
must have purpose and be able to perform that purpose).
114
“The threshold of utility is not high: An invention is ‘useful’ under section 101 if it is
capable of providing some identifiable benefit.” Juicy Whip, Inc. v. Orange Bang, Inc., 185
F.3d 1364, 1366 (Fed. Cir. 1999); see also Brooktree Corp. v. Advanced Micro Devices, Inc.,
977 F.2d 1555, 1571 (Fed. Cir. 1992) (“To violate § 101 the claimed device must be totally
incapable of achieving a useful result . . . .”); Stiftung v. Renishaw PLC, 945 F.2d 1173, 1180
(Fed. Cir. 1991) (“An invention need not be the best or the only way to accomplish a certain
result, and it need only be useful to some extent and in certain applications . . . .”).
115
See, e.g., E. I. du Pont de Nemours & Co. v. Berkley & Co., 620 F.2d 1247, 1260 n.17
(8th Cir. 1980) (“A small degree of utility is sufficient. The claimed invention must only be
capable of performing some beneficial function. An invention does not lack utility merely
because the particular embodiment disclosed in the patent lacks perfection or performs
crudely. A commercially successful product is not required. Nor is it essential that the
invention accomplish all its intended functions, or operate under all conditions, partial success
being sufficient to demonstrate patentable utility. In short, the defense of non-utility cannot
be sustained without proof of total incapacity.” (citations omitted)). Commercial success
nevertheless does play an important role in many cases in showing that an invention satisfies
the separate requirement of non-obviousness. Id. at 1263 (stating that commercial success
might be utilized as secondary consideration to determine obviousness or non-obviousness).
116
See Kitch, supra note 27, at 272 tbl.1 (showing that great stretches of time often pass
before patent grant and its commercialization).
117
See, e.g., In re Brana, 51 F.3d 1560, 1568 (Fed. Cir. 1995) (“FDA approval, however,
is not a prerequisite for finding a compound useful within the meaning of the patent laws.
Usefulness in patent law, and in particular in the context of pharmaceutical inventions,
necessarily includes the expectation of further research and development. The stage at which
an invention in this field becomes useful is well before it is ready to be administered to
humans. Were we to require Phase II testing in order to prove utility, the associated costs
would prevent many companies from obtaining patent protection on promising new
inventions, thereby eliminating an incentive to pursue, through research and development,
potential cures in many crucial areas such as the treatment of cancer.” (citations omitted)).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 425
pronounced of late. For one thing, while the utility requirement is generous, it
has its limits.
118
An invention must actually work to be considered useful, even
if it need not work especially well.
119
Moreover, the mere possibility, and
perhaps even likelihood, that some use for an invention will later be discovered
is insufficient to support a patent grant.
120
In addition, the invention must have
some demonstrated benefit, however slight. Significantly, the Supreme Court
has held that a substance cannot be considered useful merely because it is an
object of active research by scientists, who suspect it may have beneficial
properties.
121
This restriction, too, has been expanded upon and given more teeth
in recent cases.
122
So while patent law does award rights at an earlier stage in the
overall developmental process than it might, it also contains rules that limit early
awards. The utility requirement thus serves as a doctrinal tool that draws the line
between information that is and is not subject to individual ownership.
Other features of patent law also limit the availability of patents at very early
stages of the inventive process. Under a set of long-standing judge-made
exceptions to the statutory provision governing patentable subject-matter,
abstract ideas and laws of nature, though often very valuable, are categorically
excluded from patent protection.
123
Only practical applications of such
118
See Arti K. Rai, Fostering Cumulative Innovation in the Biopharmaceutical Industry:
The Role of Patents and Antitrust, 16 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 813, 839 (2001) (asserting that
only utility requirement is particularly useful in determining how far removed research is from
commercial end product to explain that strict interpretation of usefulness can be limiting).
119
See Newman v. Quigg, 877 F.2d 1575, 1581-82 (Fed. Cir. 1989) (rejecting patent for
perpetual motion device because it was inoperable and therefore lacked utility).
120
See Brenner v. Manson, 383 U.S. 519, 532-36 (1966) (explaining that patents should
not be granted on speculation of future usefulness).
121
Id. at 534-36 (“Unless and until a process is refined and developed to this point—where
specific benefit exists in currently available form—there is insufficient justification for
permitting an applicant to engross what may prove to be a broad field.”).
122
See, e.g., In re Fisher, 421 F.3d 1365, 1373 (Fed. Cir. 2005) (rejecting patent where all
“asserted uses represent mere hypothetical possibilities”); see also Utility Examination
Guidelines, 66 Fed. Reg. 1092, 1093 (proposed Jan. 5, 2001) (stating that “specific,
substantial, and credible utility” is necessary to fulfill utility requirement).
123
See Diamond v. Chakrabarty, 447 U.S. 303, 309 (1980) (“The laws of nature, physical
phenomenon, and abstract ideas have been held not patentable.”); Parker v. Flook, 437 U.S.
584, 594 (1978) (“Even though a phenomenon of nature or mathematical formulation may be
well known, an inventive application of the principle may be patented. Conversely, the
discovery of such a phenomenon cannot support a patent unless there is some other inventive
concept in its application.”); Gottschalk v. Benson, 409 U.S. 63, 67 (1972) (“Phenomena of
nature, though just discovered, mental processes, and abstract intellectual concepts are not
patentable, as they are the basic tools of scientific and technological work.”); Funk Bros. Seed
Co. v. Kalo Inoculant Co., 333 U.S. 127, 130 (1948) (“He who discovers a hitherto unknown
phenomenon of nature has no claim to a monopoly of it which the law recognizes.”); O’Reilly
v. Morse, 15 U.S. (15 How.) 62, 112-21 (1854) (explaining that one cannot patent use of
steam, however developed, as motive power for particular purpose); Le Roy v. Tatham, 14
426 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
discoveries can be patented.
124
In recent years, the Supreme Court has enforced
this constraint with particular vigor.
125
Other doctrines carry this principle
further, so that even some ideas involving practical solutions to concrete
problems are too far from practical success to be patentable. The specification
of an invention in a patent application, for instance, must enable others to make
and use the invention without resorting to “undue experimentation.”
126
As a
result, merely identifying the general form a solution to a problem will take
without actually sorting out the details necessary to put the solution into action—
think of the example of the incandescent light bulb above—is inadequate.
127
The considerations that lie behind the various doctrines used to structure the
timing of patent grants echo traditional thinking about first possession.
Awarding an exclusive right to a compound merely because it may have
beneficial properties could easily result in someone unable to discover its uses
holding the right and impeding those who could do so. Generating the new
substance is only half the battle; no rights in it will vest until at least some
practical benefit has been discovered, apart from keeping labs busy. As the
U.S. (14 How.) 156, 175 (1853) (“A principle, in the abstract, is a fundamental truth; an
original cause; a motive; these cannot be patented, as no one can claim in either of them an
exclusive right.”).
124
See Parker, 437 U.S. at 594 (stating that inventive concept in application of
phenomenon of nature may be patentable); Mackay Radio & Tel. Co. v. Radio Corp. of Am.,
306 U.S. 86, 94 (1939) (“While a scientific truth, or the mathematical expression of it, is not
patentable invention, a novel and useful structure created with the aid of knowledge of
scientific truth may be.”).
125
See Alice Corp. Pty. v. CLS Bank Int’l, 134 S. Ct. 2347, 2354, 2360 (2014) (finding
system and media claims “add nothing of substance to the underlying abstract idea” and
therefore are patent ineligible); Ass’n for Molecular Pathology v. Myriad Genetics, Inc., 133
S. Ct. 2107, 2117 (2013) (finding no patentable discovery when gene separated from
surrounding genetic material); Mayo Collaborative Servs. v. Prometheus Labs., Inc., 566 U.S.
66, 92 (2012) (finding application of natural law of relationship between concentration of
metabolites in blood and likelihood thiopurine drug will be ineffective to merely claim
underlying law of nature, and therefore be unpatentable); Bilski v. Kappos, 561 U.S. 593, 612
(2010) (finding claims that “attempt to patent the use of the abstract idea of hedging risk in
the energy market and then instruct the use of well-known analysis techniques to help
establish some of the inputs into the equation” do not sufficiently add to underlying abstract
principle).
126
In such a case, for instance, the specification of the invention in the patent application
will not enable others to make and use the invention without resorting to “undue
experimentation.” See 35 U.S.C. § 112 (2012) (“The specification shall contain a written
description of the invention, and of the manner and process of making and using it, in such
full, clear, concise, and exact terms as to enable any person skilled in the art to which it
pertains . . . to make and use the same . . . .”); In re Wands, 858 F.2d 731, 737 (Fed. Cir. 1988)
(“[E]xperimentation needed to practice the invention must not be undue experimentation.”).
127
See Incandescent Lamp Patent, 159 U.S. 465, 475-77 (1895) (finding complainant not
entitled to “monopoly of all fibrous and textile materials for incandescent conductors”).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 427
Supreme Court explained it, “[A] patent is not a hunting license. It is not a
reward for the search, but compensation for its successful conclusion.”
128
The
Court did not cite Pierson v. Post in making this pronouncement, but it might
well have. A grant prior to the development of a practical application risks
ending the race too soon. Those more capable of putting the compound to
practical use may be prevented from doing so if it is already subject to patent’s
exclusivity.
129
At the same time, an approach deeming the invention useful later in time—
upon commercialization, say—would create serious risks of either wasteful
duplication of effort or lost investment, undercutting much of the incentive to
obtain patent protection and, by hypothesis, to innovate in the first place.
130
In
the pharmaceutical context, for instance, moving from the search for some
practical application to commercialization requires clinical trials, a process that
often takes around five to seven years and involves a cost that usually exceeds
the preceding research.
131
If usefulness depended on crossing these additional
thresholds, it is more likely that pharmaceutical companies would be deterred
from joining the race to develop new drugs since there would be a greater
likelihood of losing a considerable investment if another company manages to
128
Brenner v. Manson, 383 U.S. 519, 536 (1966). Note that while the first to invent rule
of priority, in place when Brenner was decided, would grant the exclusive right to the party
who started the chase slightly earlier than its competitor, the utility requirement sets the
location of the utility bar in patent law on the broader invention procurement timeline.
129
A similar point can be made about improvements to patented inventions. If those who
discovered improvements on existing technology were precluded from obtaining patent
protection for them, in effect by granting a complete patent right to the holder of the original
patent at the moment of its issuance, the contest to develop such improvements might be
ended too soon. See Mark A. Lemley, Economics of Improvement in Intellectual Property
Law, 75 T
EX. L. REV. 989, 1000-10 (1997) (explaining that trying to improve existing
invention is integral to competitive process and that improvers must avoid literal scope of
patent claims); Robert P. Merges & Richard R. Nelson, On the Complex Economics of Patent
Scope, 90
COLUM. L. REV. 839, 872-77 (1990) (“If a property right on a basic invention covers
a host of potential improvements, the property right holder can be expected to develop the
basic invention and some of the improvements. But we would expect a single rightholder to
underdevelop—or even ignore totally—many of the potential improvements encompassed by
their broad property right.”).
130
See Duffy, supra note 15, at 445 (explaining that allowing “patenting prior to the bulk
of the investment needed to bring the innovation to market” makes competition more efficient
by “ensuring that the predominant private cost of patent racing is not the premature
expenditure of resources on developing the innovation or the duplication of innovative
efforts”).
131
See Joseph A. DiMasi, Ronald W. Hansen & Henry G. Grabowski, The Price of
Innovation: New Estimates of Drug Development Costs, 22 J.
HEALTH ECON. 151, 167 (2003)
(finding that clinical testing costs outweigh preclinical research costs per approved new drug).
428 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
complete the lengthy and expensive commercialization process more quickly.
132
A grant of exclusive rights somewhat before or around the conclusion of the
applied research phase, as current doctrine allows, promises the inventor the
right to pursue the inventive process through commercialization without the
danger of losing this investment.
133
Broadly speaking, patent doctrine strikes a
plausible balance between the dangers of early grants and the dangers of late
ones along the R&D chronology.
B. Trademark
Priority. Trademark law is a system based upon temporal priority—
conflicting claims to the same mark are resolved using a first-in-time
principle.
134
As is characteristic of such systems, parties often compete in a race
to own trademarks.
135
That first-in-time principle applies to the conduct of rival
claimants: trademark rights generally go to the first to use a distinctive
136
mark
in commerce.
137
This requirement has two elements: use and distinctiveness.
Requiring “use” of a trademark has a fairly clear connection to possession.
138
Possession is the basic precondition of use, and to use a resource is almost
132
Id. at 468-71 (detailing how probabilities will impact motivations for companies to
enter race for developing given innovation).
133
See In re Brana, 51 F.3d 1560, 1568 (Fed. Cir. 1995) (“Were we to require Phase II
testing in order to prove utility, the associated costs would prevent many companies from
obtaining patent protection on promising new inventions, thereby eliminating an incentive to
pursue, through research and development, potential cures in many crucial areas such as the
treatment of cancer.”).
134
See 15 U.S.C. § 1057(c) (2012) (stating that filing application to register mark confers
right of priority except against person who had previously used or applied to register the
mark).
135
See Zazu Designs v. L’Oreal, S.A., 979 F.2d 499, 503 (7th Cir. 1992) (“[O]ne must win
the race to the marketplace to establish the exclusive right to a mark.”).
136
See Abercrombie & Fitch Co. v. Hunting World, Inc., 537 F.2d 4, 9-10 (2d Cir. 1976)
(expounding concept of distinctiveness).
137
See Lanham Act § 1(a), 15 U.S.C. § 1051(a) (providing trademark registration for mark
“used in commerce”); U.S. PATENT & TRADEMARK OFFICE, TRADEMARK MANUAL OF
EXAMINING PROCEDURE § 900 (2018) (allowing for registration of trademark only if
application includes verified statement that mark was in use in commerce as of filing date).
But see Lanham Act § 1(b), 15 U.S.C. § 1051(b) (allowing for registration of mark based on
“intent-to-use” within six months of filing).
138
See Hanover Star Milling Co. v. Allen & Wheeler Co., 208 F. 513, 516 (7th Cir. 1913)
(detailing that trademark infringement does not damage trademark, but instead damages trade
and business by removing trademark’s meaning in use); F
RANCIS H. UPTON, A TREATISE ON
THE
LAW OF TRADE MARKS WITH A DIGEST AND REVIEW OF THE ENGLISH AND AMERICAN
AUTHORITIES 10 (1860) (“[P]roperty in trade marks, exclusive and absolute, has existed and
been recognized as a legal possession, which may be bought, and sold, and transmitted, from
the earliest days of our recorded jurisprudence.”).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 429
axiomatically to possess it.
139
Trademark law’s requirement of possession is thus
implicit in the use requirement: only one who has seized upon a distinctive mark
as the emblem of her business or its product can use it as its trademark.
140
The distinctiveness requirement adds a conceptual wrinkle. Distinctiveness
refers to a characteristic of the mark, namely its capacity to designate the source
of goods and services.
141
Protectable marks fall into two different categories.
Some are considered inherently distinctive because they are either wholly
invented, as with “fanciful” marks like Exxon, or because they do not refer to
any particular characteristic of the products they are associated, as with
“arbitrary” marks, like Apple for computers.
142
For these sorts of marks,
trademark protection begins as soon as they are used in commerce. Other marks,
however, require more. Most notably, a mark will be considered descriptive if it
connotes some characteristic of the product or service it pertains to, such as
Holiday Inn used in connection with hotels.
143
Descriptive marks are not
considered inherently distinctive and can only be protected if and when they
have “acquired distinctiveness,” often referred to as having obtained “secondary
meaning.”
144
In essence, this requires that consumers who encounter the mark
recognize that in addition to any dictionary meaning or descriptive quality—
vacation lodgings in the case of Holiday Inn—the term also designates a specific
139
The commercial aspect of the necessary use is arguably inherent in the nature of
trademarks. Trademarks are commercial emblems, and thus the kind of use that is relevant is
use as a way of designating commercial products. See Hanover Star Milling Co., 208 F. at
515 (“Use of an arbitrary and distinctive mark to indicate the origin or ownership of articles
of trade—the dealer’s ‘commercial signature’—is very old.”).
140
See id. at 515-16 (stating that “the property or right in the trade is protected from injury
by preventing a fraud-doer from stealing the complainant’s trade by means of using the
complainant’s ‘commercial signature’”).
141
See Abercrombie & Fitch Co., 537 F.2d at 8-9 (explaining that mark is distinct if it
comes to identify company, not the product, because competitors cannot be deprived of
calling product by its name).
142
See 15 U.S.C. § 1125(c)(1) (stating that “the owner of a famous mark that is distinctive,
inherently or through acquired distinctiveness” is entitled to injunctive relief if someone
causes dilution of mark); Abercrombie & Fitch Co., 537 F.2d at 11 n.17 (“[T]he term
‘fanciful,’ as a classifying concept, is usually applied to words invented solely for their use as
trademarks. When the same legal consequences attach to a common word, i.e., when it is
applied in an unfamiliar way, the use is called ‘arbitrary.’”). This also includes “suggestive”
marks, like Sunkist as applied to oranges, that may imply something about a product but stop
short of actually describing it. See Stix Prods., Inc. v. United Merchs. & Mfrs., Inc., 295 F.
Supp. 479, 488 (S.D.N.Y. 1968) (“A term is suggestive if it requires imagination, thought and
perception to reach a conclusion as to the nature of goods.”).
143
See Stix Prods., Inc., 295 F. Supp. at 488.
144
See Lanham Act § 2(f), 15 U.S.C. § 1052(f) (prohibiting registration of descriptive
marks unless acquired distinctiveness has been shown); In re Hehr Mfg. Co., 279 F.2d 526,
528 (C.C.P.A. 1960) (requiring that “unless a design is inherently distinctive it is registrable
only if sufficient evidence is presented to show it has acquired secondary meaning”).
430 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
brand.
145
Secondary meaning can develop over a period of time in which the
public gets to meet the mark in market settings such as on products and services
and in advertisement. So far as trademark law is concerned, a descriptive term
or symbol simply is not a trademark until secondary meaning has been
acquired.
146
In this way, the treatment of descriptive marks also aligns with the
rule of capture model.
Over time, there have been some adjustments to this basic model. Trademark
law has come to embrace elements of a first-committee-searcher model. In 1988,
Congress moved away from its mandatory prerequisite of actual use in
commerce. For the first time, it allowed parties, in the alternative, to reserve
exclusive rights to marks based on a mere “intent to use” them in commerce.
147
By filing an “intent to use” application, a party intending on adopting a mark
within six months (a period that can be extended up to three years, if the
applicant files periodically with the USPTO and affirms that she maintains a
bona fide intention to use the mark)
148
can protect itself against another who has
actually adopted a confusingly similar mark in commerce during that period.
This exclusivity depends on the applicant retaining its intent to use and is
conditioned on the eventual use of the mark in commerce. If the applicant fails
to use the mark in commerce within the relevant time period, the trademark
becomes free for others to adopt.
149
Thus, this statutory amendment adds a first-
committed-searcher track to claiming a trademark. For trademarks, as with
sperm whales, the prey becomes available for others to pursue if the hunter fails
to maintain pursuit. Claiming an intent to use thus signifies a change of approach
regarding priority disputes. Trademark law has evolved to allow first committed
pursuers of particular trademarks to shift the rule governing priority disputes to
a first-committed-searcher rule by filing an intent to use application and putting
all potentially competing pursuers on notice. They can secure property rights at
a relatively early point along the propertization timeline, thus enabling
themselves to end the race early and establish priority to a mark before any
145
Secondary meaning requires a showing “that the primary significance of the term in the
minds of the consuming public is not the product but the producer.” Kellogg Co. v. Nat’l
Biscuit Co., 305 U.S. 111, 118 (1938). The requirement of secondary meaning applies to a
broad range of marks, including descriptive marks, surname marks, sensory marks (sound,
sight, scent, or color marks), some geographical marks, and product configuration trade dress.
146
See Abercrombie & Fitch Co., 537 F.2d at 10 (stating descriptive terms may be
trademarked where demonstrated to be distinctive of producer’s product in commerce).
147
See Trademark Law Revision Act of 1988, 15 U.S.C. §§ 1051-1128. The Act became
effective on November 16, 1989. To some extent, this change may have curtailed what was
in effect a more generous understanding of actual use sufficient to confer priority.
148
See 37 C.F.R. § 2.89 (2018) (allowing “[e]xtensions of time for filing a statement of
use”).
149
See 15 U.S.C. § 1051(d) (requiring applicant to submit statement that mark has been
used in commerce within six months of notice of allowance).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 431
commercial use takes place.
150
Just like in the case of sperm whales, doing so
protects the first committed pursuer against third party intervention—which may
involve free-riding—in the hunting process.
Along similar lines, the rise of the “analogous use” doctrine in trademark law
signals a move away from a rule of capture approach and toward a first-
committed-searcher model when it comes to priority disputes among competing
pursuers. The analogous use doctrine allows trademark developers to claim
priority based on certain activities that make the mark known to the consuming
public—such as widespread preannouncement of a product in advertisement that
uses the mark—occurring before actual use in commerce of the good or
service.
151
Like intent-to-use applications, the doctrine of analogous use
guarantees a first committed pursuer of a mark—who might be engaging in
prerelease promotional use—priority over a second-comer who is the first to
actually use the mark in commerce.
In the case of descriptive marks, however, trademark doctrine moved in the
other direction, pushing priority disputes away from a first-committed-searcher
rule towards a rule of capture. Since descriptive marks require the development
of secondary meaning, which is often a lengthy process, the possibility of
simultaneous adoption is pronounced. Priority disputes similar to the sort
described for patent law in Figure 3 arise frequently with descriptive marks.
152
Imagine a situation in which Firm A decides to adopt a descriptive term as a
trademark and begins using it in commerce. Firm B subsequently decides to use
the same term as its own trademark and then manages to acquire secondary
meaning first, while Firm A is still working toward that goal. Between the two,
who should have an exclusive right to the mark, the one who first used the
descriptive term in commerce in a trademark-like way or the one who was the
second to use, but the first to achieve secondary meaning?
At one time, some courts and commentators advanced the idea that Firm A
should be protected against Firm Bs use, so long as Firm A’s secondary meaning
150
Id. § 1051(b) (offering protection for six months, and possibly up to three years, before
actual use in commerce as long as there is a bona fide intent to use).
151
See, e.g., Md. Stadium Auth. v. Becker, 806 F. Supp. 1236, 1239 (D. Md. 1992) (stating
that “sale of goods or services using an unregistered mark is not necessary to establish use of
the mark” and that under certain conditions advertising and promotion may suffice); Shalom
Children’s Wear, Inc. v. In-Wear A/S, 26 U.S.P.Q.2d 1516, 1519 (T.T.A.B. 1993) (“Use
analogous to trademark use . . . is nontechnical use of a trademark in connection with the
promotion or sale of a product under circumstances which do not provide a basis for an
application to register . . . . [S]uch use has consistently been held sufficient use to establish
priority rights as against subsequent users of the same or similar marks.”).
152
See, e.g., U.S. PATENT & TRADEMARK OFFICE, PROTECTING YOUR TRADEMARK:
ENHANCING YOUR RIGHTS THROUGH FEDERAL REGISTRATION 14 (2016) (explaining that
applicant may have strong rights to priority based on long use and may be able to intervene
in opposition proceeding if applicant’s rights are stronger than another applicant who applied
first).
432 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
was “in the making.”
153
In a sense, they applied a first-committed-searcher rule
to the first possession of descriptive marks: if Firm A was the first to start
pursuing secondary meaning in a descriptive term, and remained committed to
that goal, it would prevail over Firm B, who adopted the term later and then
grabbed the secondary meaning from under Firm A’s hands. In other words, they
followed the model advocated by the Pierson v. Post dissent and adopted, for
among others, sperm whales and patentable inventions prior to the AIA. Others,
however, held that in these circumstances, rights in the mark should go to Firm
B, the party who was second to join the race yet first to acquire secondary
meaning in the mark.
154
This approach can be said to follow the conception of
first possession grounded in actual capture: rights in a descriptive mark go to the
first claimant to actually acquire secondary meaning for the mark, not just to set
out and try to do so. Support for the secondary meaning in the making doctrine
eventually dissipated and today courts award priority to the first party to
complete the process of acquiring secondary meaning, regardless of whether
they were the first to begin trying.
155
Protectability. Trademark law involves choices about the timing of rights not
simply in the sense of determining which of two essentially simultaneous
competitors will receive trademark protection, but also the rights a trademark
holder will receive against remote and future rivals. For one thing, trademark
law has long given trademark holders priority not only within the confines of the
current geographic and product markets in which their marks are used but also
in those in which they are likely to expand.
156
A similar issue concerns the type
of protection received. The cornerstone of classical trademark law, for instance,
is protection against “consumer confusion,” meaning that consumers
erroneously select the wrong product, or at least have a harder time ascertaining
which of two products is the one they want. Generally speaking, trademark law
153
See Jolly Good Indus., Inc. v. Elegra Inc., 690 F. Supp. 227, 230-31 (S.D.N.Y. 1988)
(finding where secondary meaning is in making a mark will be protected against intentional
infringers); Metro Kane Imports, Ltd. v. Federated Dept. Stores, Inc., 625 F. Supp. 313, 318
(S.D.N.Y. 1985), aff’d sub nom. Metro Kane Imports v. Brookstone Co., 800 F.2d 1128 (2d
Cir. 1986) (explaining secondary meaning doctrine derives support from second comer
doctrine, which states senior user has right not to have second comer intentionally cause
confusion); 3 R
UDOLF CALLMAN, THE LAW OF UNFAIR COMPETITION, TRADEMARKS AND
MONOPOLIES 356-57 (3d ed. 1971) (“A mark with secondary meaning in-the-making should
also be protected, at least against those who appropriate it with knowledge or good reason to
know of its potential in that regard, or with an intent to capitalize on its goodwill.” (footnote
omitted)).
154
See, e.g., Cicena Ltd. v. Columbia Telecomms. Grp., 900 F.2d 1546, 1549 (Fed. Cir.
1990).
155
See Zatarain’s, Inc. v. Oak Grove Smokehouse, Inc., 698 F.2d 786, 791 (5th Cir. 1983)
(citing cases where acquiring secondary meaning established trademark rights).
156
See, e.g., AMF, Inc. v. Sleekcraft Boats, 599 F.2d 341, 349 (9th Cir. 1979) (listing
likelihood of expansion of product lines trademark infringement factor).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 433
does not protect against all uses of a word or other source signifier, but only
against those that involve its use as a trademark within the relevant market
context.
157
In recent years, however, trademark protection has expanded in a
number of ways, such as protection against uses that are likely to mislead with
respect to sponsorship or endorsement.
158
Still other provisions of trademark law
expand protection in other ways having to do with the contest over what
precisely trademark law allows to be claimed. Perhaps most notably, the Anti-
Cybersquatting Act gives trademark-holders special rights in domain names
incorporating their trademarks.
159
These are all examples of a particular kind of shift away from a rule of actual
capture toward earlier claiming. They reflect ways in which trademark law
allows “capturing” one thing—a particular trademark in a particular market—to
trigger an award of rights in something else that has not itself been captured. It
is like awarding title to fishery by virtue of having caught one of the fish within
it. In this sense, they represent an early claiming approach to the award of
trademark rights.
Trademark law also showcases another potentially useful dynamic of
institutional design where possessory rules are concerned. The basic model we
have depicted so far is essentially binary, but it is possible to use additional
points on the developmental timeline to confer additional rights. Trademark
protection is strengthened in various ways for holders of marks who have
completed steps beyond simple capture. For example, one of the factors used to
assess likelihood of confusion,
160
the lynchpin of trademark infringement, is the
strength of a trademark.
161
Trademark doctrine explicitly makes it easier for
157
Id. at 350 (identifying product market, price, and proximity as factors used to determine
infringement).
158
Anti-Cybersquatting Consumer Protection Act, 15 U.S.C. § 1125 (2012) (listing as
actionable confusion with respect to affiliation, sponsorship or approval).
159
Id. (creating cause of action against registration or use of domain name confusingly
similar to trademark). Relatedly, respecting the priority element of first possession, the Anti-
Cybersquatting Act also grants a trademark holder a superior claim to a website address even
though someone else was the first to claim and use it, if that use was not made in good faith.
See id. §1125(d)(1)(A)(i) (giving right of action for bad faith intent to profit from protected
mark similar to domain name).
160
See Sleekcraft Boats, 599 F.2d at 348-49 (setting forth non-exhaustive eight-factor test
to determine likelihood of confusion between marks).
161
For marks that are not inherently distinctive, strength is measured in terms of the degree
of secondary meaning that has been acquired. See Star Indus. v. Bacardi & Co., 412 F.3d 373,
381 (2d Cir. 2006) (“Alternatively, even if not inherently distinctive, the mark may be
distinctive by virtue of having acquired a ‘secondary meaning’ in the minds of consumers.”);
Timothy Denny Greene & Jeff Wilkerson, Understanding Trademark Strength, 16 S
TAN.
TECH. L. REV. 535, 539 (2013) (identifying brand strength as separate from trademark
strength).
434 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
owners of stronger marks to show infringement.
162
Anti-dilution law provides
an even clearer example of this tendency. In 1996, Congress amended the
Lanham Act to confer rights against having one’s trademark “diluted” by
someone else’s, even if the other person’s mark does not create any confusion
in the minds of consumers as classic trademark principles require.
163
But this
protection is available only for “famous” marks
164
and requires widespread
brand recognition among the general consuming public.
165
It goes well beyond
the level of consumer recognition and mental association sufficient to establish
secondary meaning for descriptive marks, for which recognition among a
smaller subset of consumers is sufficient.
166
To use the hunt analogy, before
rights against dilution will be awarded, trademark law requires not just capture
but something like outright slaughter. Upon the pursuer’s reaching a later point
in time in the chase chronology—the point of fame, or equivalently, upon
meeting a higher standard of performance regarding the trademark, trademark
law awards the pursuer additional property. With greater possession, one might
say, come greater rights. Note that rights against trademark dilution do not
involve the priority element of first possession, but only the protectability aspect.
In dilution settings, there is typically only one potential claimant who can argue
for nationwide fame in a particular mark, and trademark dilution doctrine
controls the award of property rights even in the absence of any actual ownership
race.
167
A similar point can be made about trademark registration. Priority in
trademark law has traditionally been geographical as well, not only temporal.
168
Rights in unregistered trademarks go to the first to use a distinctive mark in
162
Abercrombie & Fitch Co. v. Hunting World, 537 F.2d 4, 10 (2d Cir. 1976) (“The term
which is descriptive but not generic stands on a better basis.”).
163
Federal Anti-Dilution Act of 1995, Pub. L. No. 104-98, 109 Stat. 985 (codified as
amended at 15 U.S.C. §§ 1125, 1127) (“The term ‘dilution’ means the lessening of the
capacity of a famous mark to identify and distinguish goods or services.”).
164
15 U.S.C. § 1125 (c)(1) (granting dilution protection respecting “famous” marks); id.
§ 1125(c)(2) (defining when mark is famous and detailing facts to consider).
165
See id. § 1125(c)(2)(B) (listing “degree of recognition of the famous mark” as factor in
determining whether another mark is likely to cause dilution by blurring).
166
See Coach Servs., Inc. v. Triumph Learning LLC, 668 F.3d 1356, 1379 (Fed. Cir. 2012)
(identifying consumer studies as factor for consideration of whether mark has attained
secondary meaning).
167
See 15 U.S.C. § 1125 (noting that burden of proof in dilution claim first requires
proving fame).
168
See Thomas J. Carroll & Son Co. v. McIlvaine & Baldwin, 183 F. 22, 26-28 (2d Cir.
1910) (denying trademark protection for plaintiff in New York but recognizing protection
rights in Baltimore); Mark P. McKenna, The Normative Foundations of Trademark Law, 82
N
OTRE DAME L. REV. 1839, 1889 (2007) (“Other parties had the right, however, to use a mark
in other markets in which the senior user had not labored.”).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 435
commerce in a particular geographical area.
169
For example, as between a New
York user and a California user of the same unregistered mark, the rights to the
mark in Kansas go to the first to use the mark in commerce there. Federal
registration of marks, however, establishes nationwide constructive use,
conferring priority in all geographical markets, including those where the mark
has not yet been used.
170
Registration can thus be seen as awarding an exclusive
nationwide right at an early time, one that is prior to actually using the mark in
each and every jurisdiction. So while it is true that trademark law generally
requires actual use, which is akin to actual capture, to establish priority, the
availability of registration allows claiming earlier in time in new geographic
markets, thus giving the registrant the exclusive right to complete the nationwide
chase uninterrupted.
C. Copyright
Priority. On its face, copyright law does not appear to entail a priority-based
system akin to those in patent and trademark law. Copyright only protects
against copying; a copyright-holder cannot sue a second-comer who
independently generated a similar, or even identical, work.
171
But appearances
can be deceiving, and there is a more substantial priority element in copyright
law than is often realized. Suppose Picasso and Peter separately produce highly
similar paintings and it is undisputed that Picasso’s was painted a year before
Peter’s. In theory, Peter should not be liable for copyright infringement because
he created his work independently. In practice, however, he may have a hard
time making his case in court. Were Picasso to sue Peter, the court would have
no crystal ball to determine whether this was a case of independent creation or
copying. The court would likely resolve the case—as courts usually do—using
circumstantial evidence by looking to the degree of access Peter had to Picasso’s
work and the similarity between the two works.
172
The more accessible Picasso’s
painting was to Peter and the more similar Peter’s work is to Picasso’s, the more
plausible the inference that the similarities between the two resulted from
169
See Stone Creek, Inc. v. Omnia Italian Design, Inc., 875 F.3d 426, 436 (9th Cir. 2017)
(“[C]ommon-law trademark rights extend only to the territory where a mark is known and
recognized, so a later user may sometimes acquire rights in pockets geographically remote
from the first user’s territory.”).
170
Even holders of unregistered marks, moreover, enjoy priority in markets where
expansion is considered natural or likely. See United Drug Co. v. Theodore Rectanus Co., 248
U.S. 90, 99-103 (1918); Hannover Star Milling Co. v. Metcalf, 240 U.S. 403, 405-09 (1917).
171
See Sheldon v. Metro-Goldwyn Pictures Corp., 81 F.2d 49, 54 (2d Cir. 1936) (“[I]f by
some magic a man who had never known it were to compose anew Keats’s Ode on a Grecian
Urn, he would be an ‘author,’ and, if he copyrighted it, others might not copy that poem,
though they might of course copy Keats’s.”).
172
See, e.g., Arnstein v. Porter, 154 F.2d 464, 468-69 (2d Cir. 1946) (expounding on use
of circumstantial evidence in copyright infringement cases).
436 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
copying. Creators of commercially successful or other widely distributed works
are thus often able to show that the creator of a later-produced work had access
to their own earlier work.
173
The more widely distributed the earlier work is, the
greater the likelihood that courts will conclude that the alleged infringer actually
encountered the work,
174
whether she actually did so or not. Thus, in practice,
priority plays an important role in copyright law.
Note that in addition to the formal law of copyright, copyright-like rules also
develop in the informal context of social norms. Indeed, as a driver of economic
and social value, priority may be of the utmost importance, even without any
particular emphasis or importance under formal law. As between two authors—
standup comedians, for example—the first to publish or reach the market is
likely to get most of the acclaim or profit, even when the second-comer who
created independently cannot be accused of formal copyright infringement.
175
As a practical matter, a later independent creator will often reap no substantial
reputational or financial benefit from her work.
176
For these economic and social
reasons as well, copyright law involves a substantial element of priority.
The award of copyrights follows what can be thought of as a rule of capture.
177
Under copyright law as it stands today, copyright protection essentially turns on
two requirements. First, a work must be “fixed in any tangible medium of
expression,”
178
meaning that it is embodied in physical form—written down,
173
See Baxter v. MCA, Inc., 812 F.2d 421, 423 (9th Cir. 1987) (“Because direct evidence
of copying is rarely available, a plaintiff may establish copying by circumstantial evidence
of: (1) defendant’s access to the copyrighted work prior to the creation of defendant’s work,
and (2) substantial similarity of both general ideas and expression between the copyrighted
work and the defendant’s work.”).
174
Access is itself indirect evidence of exposure to the work. It is very hard to avoid
concluding that copying has occurred if the second creator actually knew the earlier work:
one cannot dream up an idea that one already has in mind, so unless a person has forgotten
something to which they were exposed before producing their own work, actual exposure will
tend to rule out the possibility of independent creation.
175
See Dotan Oliar & Christopher Sprigman, There’s No Free Laugh (Anymore): The
Emergence of Intellectual Property Norms and the Transformation of Stand-Up Comedy, 94
V
A. L. REV. 1787, 1826-27 (2008) (noting that under informal norm system among standup
comedians, ownership of joke goes to first to tell it publicly, notwithstanding formal copyright
of second comedian who created it independently).
176
See Stephen Breyer, The Uneasy Case for Copyright: A Study of Copyright in Books,
Photocopies, and Computer Programs, 84 HARV. L. REV. 281, 299-308 (1970)
(demonstrating different benefits to first creator, and also that even without copyright law
second copier may reap no benefits due to powerful position that first to reach market
possesses).
177
See Drassinower, supra note 33, at 191 (“Because it specifies the mode of acquisition
in copyright law, the originality requirement is analogous to the requirement of first
possession or occupation in property law.”).
178
See 17 U.S.C. § 102 (2012).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 437
filmed, painted, printed, and so on.
179
This requires a considerable degree of
specificity and completeness, consistent with a rule of capture. Only those works
that have been completed, in the sense of actually being recorded and preserved
in material form, are protectable.
180
Second, a work must be original.
181
This
does not require uniqueness, but it does require that the work either be created
independently of any identical work or that it depart from any materials from
which it borrows in a way that includes a minimal exercise of creativity.
182
So
while pure copying will not support copyright protection, courts do not inquire
into the aesthetic or expressive merit of a work.
183
Similar to the patent law’s
generous utility requirement, copyright requires that a claimant produce a work
having some creative element, but it need not represent a significant commercial
or artistic accomplishment.
184
It is possible to imagine a system in which the
award of rights was delayed beyond mere capture—to publication, for instance,
or a demonstration that a work is either a commercial success or a source of
substantial social value. And to the extent copying is assessed by considering
how widely the work has been distributed, priority as a practical matter is to
some extent resolved in this way. But generally speaking, copyright law
corresponds with an ordinary capture model, requiring that the work be in hand,
but not that it be cultivated or put to use.
185
Protectability. Timing issues are also affected in important ways by a variety
of rules and principles that shape the scope of copyright protection. One critical
issue involves the assignment of rights to derivative works. A derivative work is
a creation based upon one or more underlying copyrightable works, such as a
179
See Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 460-61 (1984)
(acknowledging fixed physical form to be sufficient prerequisite to copyright protection).
180
An earlier draft of a work can be protected under copyright law, however, as though it
were a final edition.
181
See 17 U.S.C. § 102 (“Copyright protection subsists, in accordance with this title, in
original works of authorship . . . .”).
182
See Feist Publ’ns, Inc. v. Rural Tel. Serv. Co., 499 U.S. 340, 345 (1991) (“Original, as
the term is used in copyright, means only that the work was independently created by the
author (as opposed to copied from other works), and that it possesses at least some minimal
degree of creativity.”).
183
See Bleistein v. Donaldson Lithographing Co., 188 U.S. 239, 251 (1903) (“It would be
a dangerous undertaking for persons trained only to the law to constitute themselves final
judges of the worth of pictorial illustrations, outside of the narrowest and most obvious
limits.”).
184
See Feist Publ’ns, Inc., 499 U.S. at 363 (“As a constitutional matter, copyright protects
only those constituent elements of a work that possess more than a de minimis quantum of
creativity.”).
185
Cf. Stewart v. Abend, 495 U.S. 207, 228-29 (1990) (stating that “nothing in the
copyright statutes would prevent an author from hoarding all of his works during the term of
the copyright”).
438 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
translation, a sequel, a movie version of a book, or an abridgement.
186
Here,
copyright law has done an about-face. Until at least the mid-nineteenth century,
rights to derivative works were often assigned to those who produced them and
were awarded only after they had been produced. A famous 1853 case, for
example, decided that the copyright to a German translation of Uncle Tom’s
Cabin belonged to the person who was first to actually produce that translation,
rather than to Harriett Beecher Stowe.
187
At that time, copyright law awarded
rights to derivative works using a rule of capture.
188
Translations were treated,
in essence, like right whales: the first person to create a translation would have
a copyright in their translation (though another independent translator would
have a copyright in whatever translation they produced).
189
Copyright in
translations attached only when the translation was completed. Under modern
copyright law, however, rights to derivative works belong to the author of the
underlying original work.
190
Ownership of derivative works is established when
the original, not the derivative work is produced.
191
The author of the underlying
original enjoys the exclusive right—secured for the limited time of the duration
of the copyright in the original—to complete the chase for any follow-on
creations, uninterrupted. So far as derivative works are concerned, copyright law
awards rights very early, at the point an author has created the underlying work
upon which the derivative is based.
192
Outside the context of derivative works, however, copyright law generally
resists such early stage awards. Copyright doctrine determines the point (on the
continuum of actions necessary to produce and disseminate a creative work) at
which an author is deemed to be in possession of the work, having made enough
progress for copyright protection to attach. In copyright infringement cases, the
critical question is often whether the plaintiff came into possession at all, and
thus ownership, of the allegedly infringed elements in her work. The chief
principle of copyright law directed to this question is embodied in the so-called
186
See 17 U.S.C. § 101 (defining derivative works).
187
See Stowe v. Thomas, 23 F. Cas. 201, 201-08 (C.C.E.D. Pa. 1853) (No. 13,514)
(holding that translation is not copying).
188
It was not until the Copyright Act of 1976 that derivative works were granted
protection. Copyright Act of 1976, Pub. L. No. 94-553, § 103, 90 Stat. 2541, 2545 (codified
at 17 U.S.C. § 103) (extending copyright protection to limited derivative works).
189
See Stowe, 23 F. Cas. at 207-08 (dismissing notion of copyright covering translation as
ridiculous).
190
17 U.S.C. § 106(2) (asserting that original copyright holder has right “to prepare
derivative works based upon the copyrighted work”).
191
See id. (asserting that completion of original work triggers rights in derivative works);
U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, COPYRIGHT IN DERIVATIVE WORKS AND COMPILATIONS 2 (2013),
https://www.copyright.gov/circs/circ14.pdf [https://perma.cc/B3HX-TCBH] (“Only the
owner of copyright in a work has the right to prepare, or to authorize someone else to create,
an adaptation of that work.”).
192
See 17 U.S.C. § 106(2) (asserting that original creator has right to prepare derivatives).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 439
idea-expression dichotomy. It is black-letter law that copyright law does not
protect “ideas,” only original expressions of them.
193
While the “idea-expression
dichotomy” seems to posit dichotomous categories, in practice the doctrine
acknowledges that idea and expression are opposing ends of a metaphorical
spectrum, and that between lies a wide and often rather murky borderland. The
classic test distinguishing unprotectable idea from protectable expression was
set out by Judge Learned Hand, in a case dealing with an original stage play and
an allegedly infringing movie having certain plot similarities:
Upon any work, and especially upon a play, a great number of patterns of
increasing generality will fit equally well, as more and more of the incident
is left out. . . . there is a point in this series of abstractions where they are
no longer protected, since otherwise the playwright could prevent the use
of his “ideas,” to which, apart from their expression, his property is never
extended.
194
Hand’s Levels of Abstraction test, as it has come to be called, can be reframed
in terms of our now-familiar possessory continuum. A playwright sets out to
write a play. She starts out with an abstract and preliminary motivating idea, and
as she moves further along the creation path she develops the plot scene after
scene, adding detail—such as names, times, places, and characters—and
gradually making her idea less abstract and more concrete. Somewhere along
this continuum of increasing concretization lies the point at which expression is
distinguished from idea. Any version of the work lying to the “left” of that point
would be regarded by copyright doctrine as an abstract idea, free for the
taking.
195
Any version of the work lying to its “right” is regarded by copyright
doctrine as an original expression, subject to possession and thus property, and
whose copying may trigger liability for infringement. The point at which an
author passes from idea to expression is copyright’s equivalent of capture. Up
to that point, the work of authorship is still evanescent. But as the author moves
across the borderline between idea and expression, she has completed the chase
and has established her property right.
196
Like the utility doctrine and the abstract idea exclusion from patentable
subject-matter, copyright’s idea-expression dichotomy seeks to ensure that
protection is awarded only after the completion of substantial steps along the
developmental timeline. In some cases, the real breakthrough—the hardest part
to achieve and the source of the greatest overall value—may lie in the general
193
See id. § 102(b) (“In no case does copyright protection for an original work of
authorship extend to any idea, procedure, process, system, method of operation, concept,
principle, or discovery . . . .”).
194
See Nichols v. Universal Pictures Corp., 45 F.2d 119, 121 (2d Cir. 1930).
195
See, e.g., Idema v. Dreamworks, Inc., 162 F. Supp. 2d 1129, 1185 (C.D. Cal. 2001)
(rejecting use of earlier drafts of screenplay to establish infringement).
196
See Edward Samuels, The Idea-Expression Dichotomy in Copyright Law, 56 TENN. L.
REV. 321, 341 (1989) (discussing “abstraction test” for explaining nature of idea-expression
dichotomy (citing Nichols, 45 F.2d at 121)).
440 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
concept. One writer or musician’s work may spawn an entire genre of
subsequent works, a creative style, or a go-to technique. But the view taken in
copyright is that this is not sufficient. A genre cannot exist on its own, without
works embodying it concretely, and it is only when those works are completed
that protection arises. Only an author actually in possession of a specific,
concrete expression of a general idea can claim copyright protection.
III. G
RASPING POSSESSION
This Article has thus far shown that IP doctrines can be analogized to first
possession rules, both conceptually and in terms of their underlying functional
foundations. This Part now explores implications. The previously described
framework suggests ways to think about some pressing current questions in
intellectual property and to evaluate the way the law has developed in recent
years. In the discussion that follows, this Part begins by looking at several
specific IP rules and policies that affect the initial award of IP rights. Outlining
an integrative and prescriptive analysis of original acquisition in intellectual
property across doctrinal boundaries, this Part offers some broader observations
about the challenges of intellectual property and its relationship to the institution
of property.
A. Doctrinal Implications
1. Patent Trolls: Of Abstract Ideas and Inter Partes Review
Much patent law and policy in recent years has centered on perceived
problems associated with the phenomena variously referred to as patent assertion
entities (“PAEs”), non-practicing entities, or, most pejoratively, patent trolls.
There is some disagreement about how exactly to define a patent “troll” and
what the trouble with them actually is. The major concern with PAEs, one that
was discussed by the Supreme Court, is that they profit by wielding hold-out
leverage in cases where the patent at issue covers a relatively insignificant aspect
of a much larger product, a problem that is particularly serious when notice of
the patent was inadequate during the process of product development.
197
Another line of criticism associates patent trolling with nuisance or strike suits,
where defendants settle infringement actions involving “weak” or bad patents
simply because it is cheaper than litigating.
198
While some highlight certain
197
See eBay Inc. v. MercExchange, L.L.C., 547 U.S. 388, 396 (2006) (Kennedy, J.,
concurring) (suggesting injunctive relief should be denied “[w]hen the patented invention is
but a small component of the product the companies seek to produce and the threat of an
injunction is employed simply for undue leverage in negotiations”).
198
See id. at 397 (noting “potential vagueness and suspect validity” of some business
method patents).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 441
social benefits associated with PAEs,
199
a recent study by the Federal Trade
Commission voiced concerns about the business model of litigation-reliant
PAEs, which tend to obtain litigation settlements that “might be considered
nuisance value.”
200
The aforementioned major concern with PAEs can be understood within the
framework developed here: it is simply the problem of premature allocation of
patent rights. As discussed above, a danger in early awards of property rights is
that they may be given to parties who are initially leading the chase but who are
eventually incapable of completing it successfully. As mentioned, such early
misallocations involve subsequent transaction costs, in this case the cost of
licensing the patents, under the threat and cost of pending litigation, to practicing
entities who have often developed the same technology independently. The costs
further involve the taxing of, or disincentivizing of, the activity of such capable,
practicing entities. The proper solution to patent trolling is therefore pushing the
moment of the patent grant to a later stage by requiring the performance of
further steps along the patent’s prospect before exclusive rights are granted. The
natural and preferred way to do so doctrinally would be to invigorate the utility
prerequisite to patentability, which is currently very low. Unfortunately, the
legal system has treated the problem only symptomatically thus far.
The legal system has responded to concerns about patent trolls in at least two
major ways. The first, a judicial response, is the Supreme Court’s renewed
emphasis on non-statutory exclusions from the domain of patentable subject
matter for natural laws and abstract ideas, which appears to have resulted in a
significant reduction in patents issued in areas like software and business
methods.
201
The second, a legislative response, is the expansion of mechanisms
that permit the USPTO to reconsider and cancel issued patents—chiefly through
the inter partes review and post-grant review procedures, commonly referred to
as “IPRs” and “PGRs.”
202
Both the expansion of patentable subject-matter
exclusions and procedures for expanded administrative review of patents can be
understood as measures that delay the award of patent rights, albeit in different
ways. Both reforms, however, show signs of a failure to appreciate the larger set
of concerns and policy tradeoffs relevant to timing the award of IP rights and
199
See, e.g., Michael Risch, Patent Troll Myths, 42 SETON HALL L. REV. 457, 491 (2012).
200
See FTC, PATENT ASSERTION ENTITY ACTIVITY: AN FTC STUDY 8-9 (2016) (giving
statistics showing early settlement in patent suits brought by PAEs).
201
See Alice Corp. v. CLS Bank Int’l, 134 S. Ct. 2347, 2354 (2014) (describing Supreme
Court’s willingness to understand 35 U.S.C. § 101 (2012) as having “exclusionary principle”);
Mayo Collaborative Servs. v. Prometheus Labs., Inc., 566 U.S. 66, 70 (2012) (“‘[L]aws of
nature, natural phenomena, and abstract ideas’ are not patentable.” (quoting Diamond v.
Diehr, 450 U.S. 157, 185 (1981))).
202
See 35 U.S.C. § 311 (2012) (outlining procedure for IPRs of issued patents); id. § 321
(outlining procedures for PGRs of issued patents).
442 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
could be modified to respond to the challenges of early awards while better
avoiding the drawbacks of later ones.
The patentable subject-matter exclusions reflect an emphasis on applied uses
and a concern that principles and knowledge should not be withdrawn from the
public domain.
203
It is not enough to come up with an application of a newly
discovered scientific principle or a newly created mathematical algorithm if the
process of adapting those ideas into a practical application is itself purely
obvious or routine. The Court’s instinct is firmly grounded in basic principles of
patent law. Patent law is concerned only with practical applications, rather than
general truths about the world, and should therefore only award protection when
such an application has been developed.
204
Furthermore, a patent on the
application of such a general truth can sometimes amount to what is in effect a
patent on a general truth itself, which may frustrate the overall goals of the patent
system by inhibiting further discovery and innovation.
205
The Supreme Court’s
concern that the patentable subject-matter exclusions not be evaded through
artful drafting
206
is perfectly sound.
But the reason for those exclusions must be kept in mind. Important
discoveries about the world are excluded from patent protection in order to
facilitate further discovery and the development of practical uses thereof. The
Supreme Court’s announced test for separating the abstract from the practical
essentially asks how much value and innovation of a particular invention resides
in the a novel principle’s implementation, as distinguished from the principle
itself.
207
But if the concern is to ensure, on the one hand, that the hunt really is
completed and, on the other, that others remain free to compete for those prey
not yet captured, this test misses the mark. Rather than focusing on the relative
proportions of abstract knowledge versus practical insight in a particular
invention, it would make more sense to consider the extent to which protection
for a particular application would in practice amount to protection of the
203
See Bilski v. Kappos, 561 U.S. 593, 612 (2010) (dismissing patent claim as abstract
idea).
204
See Brenner v. Manson, 383 U.S. 519, 536 (1966) (stating that “patent system must be
related to the world of commerce rather than to the realm of philosophy”).
205
See Mayo Collaborative Servs., 566 U.S. at 86 (“[T]here is a danger that the grant of
patents that tie up their use will inhibit future innovation premised upon them, a danger that
becomes acute when a patented process amounts to no more than an instruction to ‘apply the
natural law,’ or otherwise forecloses more future invention than the underlying discovery
could reasonably justify.”).
206
See id. at 72 (“[T]o transform an unpatentable law of nature into a patent-eligible
application of such a law, one must do more than simply state the law of nature while adding
the words ‘apply it.’”).
207
See Alice Corp. v. CLS Bank Int’l, 134 S. Ct. 2347, 2355 (2014) (describing the
Supreme Court’s two-step process for determining patent eligibility); Mayo Collaborative
Servs., 566 U.S. at 82 (denying patent for simply instructing application of known natural
law).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 443
unpatentable principle. So, for example, in Mayo Collaborative Services v.
Prometheus Laboratories, Inc.,
208
a patent essentially reciting certain
discoveries about human metabolism and only obliquely suggesting anything
particular be done with those discoveries presents a serious risk that any other
useful application of the biological facts discovered will infringe the patent,
including those that do not reflect genuine “improvement[s]” upon it.
209
When a patentee really has developed a useful application of a principle, the
patent chase ought to be considered over, so far as that application is concerned.
The real problem lies in the possibility that by claiming a particular specimen,
the patentee will have de facto rights to a larger genus. Particularly in the context
of process patents—where most of the mischief is thought to reside—the
giveaway is usually in the verbs. Where the action that is described or called for
is vague, there is a serious danger that the patent will cover not simply a
particular application but a wider array of uses of a more general principle. Mayo
Collaborative Services involved a patent purporting to claim a method of
medical treatment, but whose central instruction to those performing it was that
a specified level of a particular compound present in certain medical patients
“indicates a need” to increase their drug dosage, while another specified level
“indicates a need” to decrease it.
210
The phrasing was highly abstract; the verb
referred to the compound itself, rather than to anyone who would carry out the
method. There was therefore an obvious risk that the patent would apply not to
a particular way that a fact about human metabolism might be put to use, but to
a set of essentially unrelated uses of that information. In other words, the
doctrine governing exclusions of natural laws and abstract ideas should function
more like the patent equivalent of copyright’s merger doctrine, which bars
copyright protection when protecting a particular expression of an unprotectable
idea would effectively wall off any expression of the idea.
211
The guiding
concern ought to be the likelihood that patent protection will tie up general
research and the development of novel applications unrelated to the particular
application invented by the patentee.
While patentable subject-matter exclusions push patentability later in time
conceptually speaking, IPRs and PGRs push the grant of patent protection later
in a more practical sense. Although it has always been possible to challenge the
validity of a patent in actual patent litigation, IPRs and PGRs have significantly
expanded the ability to oppose patent grants while still in an administrative
setting. In practice the effect has been to open up the question of validity
substantially so that, in some sense, it is much more uncertain whether a patent
208
566 U.S. 66 (2012).
209
See id. at 67-69; see also 35 U.S.C. § 101 (2012) (listing improvement as necessity for
patent).
210
Mayo Collaborative Servs., 566 U.S. at 75.
211
See Baker v. Selden, 101 U.S. 99, 102 (1879) (decrying copyright claim for particular
accounting system using ruled lines as fraud against public).
444 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
is ever valid. Bad patents are, of course, bad, and weeding them out is
unobjectionable so far as it goes. As previously stated, early awards risk
assigning patents to a party that is not able to follow through with a useful
application. They may reward unhelpful research activity intended to obtain a
patent whose value derives overwhelmingly from holding up the activities of
others. But later awards have their costs too—disincentivizing innovation for
fear of invalidation and duplication of effort. Indeed, with the recent enactment
of the first, general, federal law of trade secrecy,
212
the net effect of these
changes may be a significant shift of incentives away from public disclosure of
inventions to their secret practice in some fields.
2. The Hunt for Secondary Meaning
Concerns about premature claiming have also resulted in confusion in
trademark law, particularly as it relates to the doctrine of secondary meaning in
the making, discussed earlier.
213
The now-discarded secondary meaning in the
making doctrine would have created something like a first-committed-searcher
rule for descriptive marks. This analysis suggests two conclusions about the
doctrine.
First, while rejecting the doctrine was likely the right result, it was reached
for the wrong reason. In essence, opponents argued that any recognition of
incipient secondary meaning was “inimical” to the purpose of trademark law.
214
To protect a party that is merely working toward acquiring secondary meaning
in a mark, it was said, flies in the face of trademark law’s commitment to
protecting marks only when they were, in fact, marks—devices that distinguish
one class of products from another. But this overlooks the difference between
the two modes of establishing possession that we have explored. A first-
committed-searcher rule gives a party who already began the chase priority over
212
See Defend Trade Secrets Act of 2016, Pub. L. No. 114-153, 130 Stat. 376 (codified in
scattered sections of 18 U.S.C.).
213
See supra notes 136-37 and accompanying text.
214
See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF UNFAIR COMPETITION § 13 cmt. e (AM. LAW INST. 1995)
(“The [secondary meaning in the making] doctrine, if taken literally, is inimical to the purpose
of the secondary meaning requirement.”); see also Laureyssens v. Idea Grp., Inc., 964 F.2d
131, 138 (2d Cir. 1992) (“Moreover, ‘[t]he doctrine, if taken literally, is inimical to the
purpose of the secondary meaning requirement.’” (quoting R
ESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF
UNFAIR COMPETITION § 13 cmt. e (AM. LAW INST. 1995))); Joel S. Armstrong, Secondary
Meaning “In the Making” in Trademark Infringement Actions Under Section 43(a) of the
Lanham Act, 14 G
EO. MASON L. REV. 603, 619 (1992) (“The secondary meaning in the making
doctrine is therefore rejected as being inimical to the theoretical and economic underpinnings
of trademark law.”); Willajeanne F. McLean, The Birth, Death, and Renaissance of the
Doctrine of Secondary Meaning in the Making, 42 A
M. U. L. REV. 737, 757 (1993) (“Legal
scholars opposed to the doctrine of secondary meaning in the making thought that the doctrine
was generally ‘inimical to the purpose of . . . secondary meaning’ . . . .” (quoting
R
ESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF UNFAIR COMPETITION § 13 cmt. e (AM. LAW INST. 1995))).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 445
later entrants, and possibly some rights against interference, but it need not entail
full, permanent rights of exclusion without further development of the resource.
A whaler in hot pursuit of a sperm whale has priority over other whalers, but he
does not come to own the whale unless the chase is actually completed within a
fairly compressed timeframe. Indeed, this very fact is evident in trademark law
itself: while an intent-to-use application secures priority in a mark, no action for
infringement can be brought until that mark has actually been used in
commerce.
215
The logic of the argument used to defeat legal recognition of
incipient secondary meaning would essentially deny the possibility of a first-
committed-searcher standard in first possession doctrine.
Nevertheless, not recognizing a secondary meaning in the making doctrine
for descriptive marks is justified in our view because of the difficulty courts
would face defining who is a “committed” searcher. Importantly, there is no
clear way for a court to set a time limit on a party’s attempt to acquire secondary
meaning. This problem is less acute for resources like whales. The timeframe at
issue is relatively short—a few days at most—and the first committed whaler
must be in hot pursuit, which, though certainly not free from of any ambiguity
or exercise of judgment, nevertheless has a fairly apparent meaning where
pursuit is not just a metaphor but a simple physical fact. The process of building
a brand, by contrast, is much less straightforward. There is no clear timeframe
in which to complete the process of developing secondary meaning, given
differences in marketing techniques and strategies, the marketing channels
appropriate to different products, the structure of the market, and the cross-
section of the consuming public to be targeted. Since it would be difficult for
courts to develop a standard by which to measure the commitment to following
through, the secondary meaning in the making doctrine involved the risk of
granting rights in a mark to a party that would not eventually develop such
secondary meaning while denying these rights to a rival party who did.
Second, contrary to what the courts rejecting a secondary meaning in the
making doctrine supposed, the problem is not one that is somehow conceptually
intrinsic to trademark law. While courts may not be positioned to initiate such
changes, the story may be different for Congress. It is possible to adopt a
possession rule based on a first-committed-searcher model and grant rights
earlier in the development process if a proper system of registration is
established in order to provide adequate notice to others. This can be
accomplished practically only by legislation. Legislation can address the proper
limitations on such a system—the time window necessary to establish secondary
meaning and the degree of diligence that must be shown to remain in “hot
pursuit.” Indeed, intent to use applications represent a legislative intervention
that has just these features and can be used today by first committed adopters of
descriptive marks. This institutional innovation provides both the notice to
215
See 15 U.S.C. § 1114 (2012); 1-800 Contacts, Inc. v. WhenU.com, Inc., 414 F.3d 400,
412 (2d Cir. 2005) (clarifying that “use,” “in commerce,” and “likelihood of confusion” are
three distinct elements necessary for establishing trademark infringement).
446 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
others about the committed search and a time limit for the completion of the
hunt.
B. Institutional Implications
These reflections on existing doctrine and the general framework this Article
develops point toward some larger observations about first possession in IP law.
The analogy to first possession helps us to see the stakes at issue when it comes
to the rules that determine the award of IP rights, but there are also important
differences in the way those concerns play out that shed light on the deeper
structure of both IP law and the first possession mechanism more generally.
1. Possession, Information, and Intellectual Property
Recall that first-committed-searcher rules can minimize wasteful duplication
of effort and mitigate the disincentive effects that could otherwise result because
of the risk that substantial investments made to claim a resource will be lost if
someone else wins the contest for it. An effective first-committed-searcher rule
ends the race when one of the contenders reaches a point where eventual capture
is likely, and thus saves on what would otherwise be duplicative and wasteful
simultaneous search and investment efforts in an ongoing race.
This advantage of the first-committed-searcher rule depends critically on the
ability to give notice to others that the race has in fact ended, and indeed, on the
confidence of competitors for a resource that they will be informed when and if
the race ended.
216
With physical resources, it is easy to overlook the importance
of this precondition. In general, it is relatively easy for one person trying to
capture or develop a physical resource to learn that someone else is also doing
the same. In Pierson v. Post, for instance, it appears to have been entirely clear
to Pierson that Post was chasing the fox.
217
Similarly, it would generally be
apparent to a whaler who happened upon a sperm whale that a rival was already
in hot pursuit and managed to harpoon it.
The same cannot be said of intellectual property. Since firms often conduct
R&D in private—indeed, often in secret—one firm could easily undertake
extensive work to develop a cure for a given disease or plan an advertising
campaign centering on a new trademark without knowing that a competitor up
the street was doing the very same thing.
218
Telling the firms that the first
committed searcher will be protected against later pursuers of the resource does
216
Kitch, supra note 27, at 266 (suggesting that to create efficient system there must be
communication of information to competing firms at efficient rate, such as publicly recorded
ownership of patents shortly after discovery).
217
Pierson v. Post, 3 Cai. 175, 175 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1805) (“Pierson, well knowing the fox
was so hunted and pursued, did, in the sight of Post, to prevent his catching the same, kill and
carry it off.”).
218
Kitch, supra note 27, at 278 (“Under a regime of trade secrecy, the competitive firm
might never learn of a competitor’s processes and would not learn of the technology
incorporated in a new product until it was marketed.”).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 447
not do much to reduce duplicative search efforts, for example, if race participants
cannot figure out if someone else’s search is already underway before choosing
to embark on it themselves.
Absent registration, for instance, firms planning to introduce products or
services under a particular branding scheme face the very real possibility that
some other business will enter the market ahead of them using a similar set of
emblems. Preparing to launch is often a very costly investment that involves the
choice of a mark, the preparation and timing of a pre-launch campaign, and
potentially inscribing the mark on tens of thousands of items—athletic shoes,
computers, soda bottles, and so on—in advance of shipment. The risk that these
efforts would have to be scrapped would be a very serious problem for firms
contemplating intensive marketing campaigns. While races for physical
resources governed by a first-committed-searcher rule tend to be conducted
under conditions of relatively symmetric information that forestalls wasteful
investment, this is not generally as likely with intellectual property.
The vital role played by centralized registries in IP law responds to this
difficulty by offering an independent mechanism to supply notice without
relying on actions taken in the course of the race alone. In trademark law, the
creation of intent-to-use applications allows a company to inform all others that
it is in hot pursuit of a particular branding space.
219
And even before intent-to-
use applications were introduced, courts took advantage of ordinary registration
based on actual use of a mark to address information concerns, interpreting the
requirement of use in commerce somewhat more leniently for registered marks
than for unregistered ones. Registered marks still required some degree of use
in order to prevent firms from grabbing marks without actually doing anything
productive with them—failure to follow through, in other words.
220
But
registered marks require less use than unregistered marks because registered
marks gave notice to the world that limited commercial sales did not.
221
Trademark law’s traditional use in commerce requirement is thus justified not
only as a waste prevention feature, but also on informational grounds. Use in
commerce puts competitors on notice that the mark is being used. As Judge
Easterbrook explained in a well-known opinion, registering a mark enables
parties to negotiate over the mark before one of them unwittingly “commit[s]
large sums to marketing,” only to discover someone else claimed it first.
222
219
See 15 U.S.C. § 1051(b)-(d) (describing process for applying for bona fide intent-to-
use trademark).
220
See Zazu Designs v. L’Oreal, S.A., 979 F.2d 499, 503 (7th Cir. 1992) (“By insisting
that firms use marks to obtain rights in them, the law prevents entrepreneurs from reserving
brand names in order to make their rivals’ marketing more costly.”).
221
Id. (“Registration modifies this system slightly, allowing slight sales plus notice in the
register to substitute for substantial sales without notice.”).
222
Id. at 504 (“Liberality in registering marks is not problematic, because the registration
gives notice to latecomers, which token use alone does not. Firms need only search the register
448 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
Public sales similarly “let others know that they should not invest resources to
develop a mark similar to one already used in the trade.”
223
Intent-to-use bsaed
registration carried this model a step further, making it possible to move the
priority point back even earlier, from slight sales to no sales at all, while at the
same time requiring that substantial sales follow in relatively short order.
224
Intent-to-use applications overcome the notice problem that is so acute for first-
committed-searcher rules in intellectual property, and thereby enable the law to
respond more effectively to the problems associated with insisting on actual
capture. Thus understood, one reason for the common law prevalence of the rule
of capture versus the first-committed-searcher rule is likely informational: actual
capture of physical resources is a clear informational signal, in a way “a first
committed searcher” is not. But once it is possible to give notice to third
parties—such as through registries—the first-committed-searcher rule becomes
a more viable alternative.
A similar dynamic has happened in copyright law under a slightly different
heading. In certain contexts, creators working to bring a work to the public have
had to confront a serious risk that the work would be leaked to the public before
its official release, in effect snatching an important aspect of the work from their
hands in a manner not unlike the taking of the fox in Pierson v. Post. Until
relatively recently, that was the case with copyrighted works. The often-critical
statutory damages remedy was only available if the work infringed was already
completed and registered with the copyright office. Since registration requires
deposit of the work, copyright owners could not, practically speaking, register
until the work was completely finished.
225
In the well-known Harper & Row,
Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enterprises
226
case, for example, the famous
publishing house was set to release Gerald Ford’s presidential memoir and
sought to whet the public’s appetite for the book by allowing Time Magazine to
print a few select excerpts in advance of release.
227
Another magazine, however,
managed to obtain a “purloined copy” of the memoir and rushed to publish the
juiciest portions, preempting Time’s publication.
228
Harper & Row sued and won
before embarking on development. Had ZHD registered ZAZÚ, the parties could have
negotiated before L’Oréal committed large sums to marketing.”).
223
Id. at 503.
224
See 15 U.S.C. § 1051(b)-(d) (requiring registrant file verified statement that mark is in
use in commerce within six months after allowance of intent-to-use application).
225
17 U.S.C. §§ 407-408 (2012) (requiring owners of copyright to deposit copies of
protected work within three months after publication of work). Theoretically, copyright
owners could register versions of a work periodically while they were working on it and thus
avail themselves of the statutory damages remedy, but this practice would be costly,
monetarily and organizationally, and not very practical.
226
471 U.S. 539 (1985).
227
Id. at 539.
228
Id. at 539-40 (“[P]etitioners, as the copyright holders, negotiated a prepublication
licensing agreement with Time Magazine under which Time agreed to pay $25,000 ($12,500
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 449
a judgment of infringement, but the company was ultimately unable to recover
statutory damages, making its victory rather limited. In another major prerelease
infringement incident in 2003, a non-final version of the movie “Hulk” leaked
to the Internet prior to official release, resulting in a harm that the studio claimed
amounted to sixty-six million dollars.
229
In 2005, following the Hulk incident, Congress amended the Copyright Act
to add a provision allowing for the preregistration of “works being prepared for
commercial distribution.”
230
Under this new statutory framework, a party who
has begun the process of generating a creative work can preregister it prior to
completion, making it possible to recover statutory damages and attorney’s fees
for any subsequent act of infringement.
231
The preregistrant must eventually
follow up and r
egister the work once published,
232
although, surprisingly, the
Copyright Act does not set a time limit for completing the work and publishing
it.
Preregistration gives authors security to complete the chase without
interruption by substantially increasing the sanctions on the “saucy intruder,” in
the language of the Pierson v. Post dissent.
233
It marks the limited introduction
of a first-committed-searcher model. Observed patterns of use of copyright
preregistration claiming are consistent with what the theory developed in this
Article predicts: early claiming becomes more attractive as the “hunt” becomes
more expensive, since higher costs are more likely to deter firms concerned
in advance and the balance at publication) in exchange for the right to excerpt 7,500 words
from Mr. Ford’s account of his pardon of former President Nixon.”).
229
See Troy Graham, N.J. Man, 24, Is Sentenced for Net Bootleg of ‘The Hulk, PHILA.
INQUIRER, Sept. 27, 2003, at B1 (“Vivendi Universal Entertainment, which produced The
Hulk, commissioned several studies to determine what Gonzalez’s actions cost the studio.
While assigning a dollar amount is an inexact science, the studio settled on about $66 million
in a victim-impact statement to the federal court.”). For another example, see Rebecca Pahle,
A Brief History of Movies Being Leaked Onto the Internet, F
ILM JOURNAL (Dec. 5, 2014),
http://www.filmjournal.com/content/brief-history-movies-being-leaked-internet
[https://perma.cc/K5MN-5UJC] (illustrating multiple instances of movies being leaked before
official release).
230
See 17 U.S.C. § 408(f) (“[T]he Register of Copyrights shall issue regulations to
establish procedures for preregistration of a work that is being prepared for commercial
distribution and has not been published.”).
231
On preregistration, see Dotan Oliar & Nicholas Matich, Copyright Preregistration:
Evidence and Lessons from the First Seven Years, 2005-2012, 55 ARIZ. L. REV. 1073, 1073
(2013) (“Preregistering a work allows copyright owners immediate access to courts and an
expanded menu of remedies.”).
232
See 17 U.S.C. § 408(f)(3) (requiring registration no later than three months after
publication of work).
233
Pierson v. Post, 3 Cai. 175, 181 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1805) (Livingston, J., dissenting) (“But
who would . . . pursue the windings of this wily quadruped, if . . . a saucy intruder, who had
not shared in the honours or labours of the chase, were permitted to come in at the death, and
bear away in triumph the object of pursuit?”).
450 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
about losing their investments if someone else beats them to the punch. Movies
are generally the most expensive copyrighted works to create, and,
unsurprisingly, they are the category for which preregistrations is most
consistently used.
234
Again, however, this earlier protection centers on a
registration regime.
Copyright preregistration does not yield the first-committed-searcher rule’s
advantage of deterring a bona fide third party from entering the race, here via
independent creation. But it does entail another benefit associated with this rule,
namely assuring (or increasing the assurance of) the first committed searcher
against a third party’s interference throughout the course of the hunt, while free
riding on the first pursuer’s effort. True, in this context there is no danger that a
third party will own the copyright rather than the creator, as the third party is an
infringer and the owner’s formal copyright is not in danger. However, it is of
little consequence to the copyright owner by which mechanism the value of her
investment went to zero. She wishes to secure the fruits of her investment, and
the enhanced remedies that preregistration confers tend to do so, thus
maintaining her incentives to make costly investments.
The relationship between notice considerations and the timing of exclusive
rights is perhaps most apparent in the patent context. Although U.S. patent law
followed a first-committed-searcher model until enactment of the AIA, its ability
to shore up incentives to innovate and discourage waste in the development
process was undercut by informational barriers. To return once again to the
situation described in Figure 3, the pre-AIA regime tended to encourage both
Tesla and Edison to carry out the entire inventive process, even though the
priority rules followed a first-committed-searcher model. Unless Tesla had some
way of knowing that Edison came up with the idea first and was diligently
attempting to see it through to its conclusion, Tesla would often see no reason
not to carry out the entire inventive process simultaneously to its end, only to
discover that he was actually the second pursuer. Such surprise would not arise
in first-committed-searcher rule races over physical resources: any onlooker
would readily see whether a sperm whale is at large or is rather being hotly
pursued.
One may wonder how such a seemingly inefficient aspect of our patent system
survived for so long? It turns out that for a good part of the nineteenth century,
starting with the Patent Act of 1836, patent doctrine had a mechanism that helped
inventors receive timely notice of others’ pursuits. By filing a so-called “patent
caveat,” inventors were entitled to receive notice from the patent office
whenever a rival inventor filed a patent application for inventions that were
234
See Oliar & Matich, supra note 231, at 1100 (“The film industry is both the industry
most likely to benefit from preregistration and the system’s most consistent commercial
user.”).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 451
similar to those the caveat filer was working on.
235
Caveats were eventually
abolished in 1910, and without them a first-to-invent patent system makes less
sense. In their absence, a first-to-file system, such as the AIA, is preferable on
notice grounds. The touchstone of priority under the AIA is disclosure, whether
by filing with the patent office or by making the invention or information about
it available to the public in a context where someone having skill in the relevant
art might be likely to look.
236
To that extent, the AIA makes a good deal of sense.
2. Intellectual Property as Property: Flexibility and Standardization
With the AIA, patent law adopted an actual capture rule to govern the award
of exclusive rights, thereby coming into alignment with the general approach
taken in copyright and trademark law. But since not all whales are subject to the
same rule of first possession,
237
we might well ask whether one rule should apply
uniformly across either patent law or IP law more widely.
The fact that our patent system has—or had—mechanisms that awarded the
right to the first committed searcher makes sense in light of the theory of
possession developed here. Patents are very often extremely expensive to
acquire in a way copyrights by and large are not.
238
The pharmaceutical
company Amgen spends an average of $3.7 billion on R&D for every drug that
it has approved; AstraZeneca spends more than four times as much.
239
The
likelihood that these investments will be lost is also higher. The probability of
two inventors discovering the same technology is higher than the probability of
235
See John F. Duffy, Embryonic Inventions and Embryonic Patents: Prospects,
Prophesies, and Pedis Possessio, in PERSPECTIVES ON COMMERCIALIZING INNOVATION 234,
263-64 (F. Scott Kieff & Troy A. Paredes eds., 2011) (“By filing a caveat, a party was entitled
to notice from the Patent Office if any other party filed a patent application on the same subject
matter described in the caveat.”).
236
See 35 U.S.C. § 112 (2012) (detailing disclosure requirements of patent application);
see also id. § 102(b)(1)(A) (providing priority through grace period exceptions for disclosures
by applicant or third party who received disclosed information from applicant).
237
Compare Ellickson, supra note 45, at 90-94 (describing “iron-holds-the-whale” rule
wherein whale is owned by first party to attach harpoon to whale), with Swift v. Gifford, 23
F. Cas. 558, 559-60 (D. Mass. 1872) (comparing different standards for rule of capture of
whales generally with that of the sperm whale species).
238
The cost of producing copyrighted works is not as obvious as it might seem. Subject to
certain caveats, across-the-board increases in the compensation to producers of creative works
should in principle always result in greater creative output, though the costs, including both
access and opportunity costs, may not be worth it.
239
See DiMasi, supra note 131, at 151 (“The estimated average out-of-pocket cost per new
drug is US$ 403 million (2000 dollars).”); Matthew Herper, The Truly Staggering Cost of
Inventing New Drugs, FORBES MAGAZINE (Feb. 10, 2012, 7:41 AM),
https://www.forbes.com/sites/matthewherper/2012/02/10/the-truly-staggering-cost-of-
inventing-new-drugs/#704dda74a948 [https://perma.cc/E85P-BBE7] (presenting research
spending per new drug for several major pharmaceutical companies).
452 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
two creators generating the same creative work, since the inventive solution is
dictated and constrained by real-world functional considerations. It seems far
more probable that two firms would both invent acetylsalicylic acid (aspirin)
than that two painters would both paint Starry Night.
Inventors also face a more serious threat from products and ideas similar to
their own. Consumers will often be indifferent as between two technologies that
do the same thing by different means, treating one as a substitute for the other.
If George decides to purchase a gas stove for his kitchen, he is unlikely to
purchase an electric stove too; if he takes Zocor to reduce his cholesterol, he is
unlikely to take Lipitor as well. By contrast, demand for creative works is less
likely to be mutually exclusive. A person might want to see all the superhero
movies Hollywood can produce in a year. Indeed, rather than suppress demand,
one superhero movie may stimulate demand for others.
For all these reasons, we would generally expect inventors to need greater
protection from competitors during the process of generating their intellectual
goods than creators of artistic works. Simply put, developing new
pharmaceuticals often costs hundreds of millions of dollars,
240
and firms will
often be reluctant to proceed unless they have sufficient confidence they will
reap the rewards if those investments do indeed produce results.
241
In copyright,
ownership and priority are generally determined by the moment of capture,
fixation of particular expression in a physical copy.
242
Translating to the
terminology of patent law, this is essentially the point where creative
abstractions are reduced to actual practice. On average, the costs of copyrighted
works are less than those of patents, and the claiming moment is later, as the
theory this Article proposes would suggest.
Yet not all patents and not all copyrights are alike. While some patents are
extremely expensive to procure, not all of them are so. And some creative
works—think of Hollywood blockbusters—require huge investments. There can
be substantial variability in costs across different kinds of IP products, and some
patents may look more like the typical copyright, and some copyrights like the
more investment-intensive patents. Software or business method patents are
probably less costly to come up with than the average pharmaceutical patent.
Movies or software are more expensive to produce than the average haiku.
That not all whales are alike, and that different ones are subject to different
doctrines of first possession, suggests that perhaps a degree of differentiation
240
See DiMasi, supra note 131, at 151 (“Capitalizing out-of-pocket costs to the point of
marketing approval at a real discount rate of 11% yields a total pre-approval cost estimate of
US$ 802 million (2000 dollars).”); Herper, supra note 239 (“The average drug developed by
a major pharmaceutical company costs at least $4 billion, and it can be as much as $11
billion.”).
241
See Duffy, supra note 15, at 469-75 (providing numerical calculations to show when
theoretical firms may refrain from investment due to uncertain return).
242
17 U.S.C. § 302 (2012) (“Copyright in a work . . . subsists from its creation
and . . . endures for a term consisting of the life of the author and 70 years after the author’s
death.”).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 453
may be appropriate also with respect to particular doctrines that govern the
claiming of any one type of IP right. Given that the greater levels of investment
offer more reason to adopt early claiming, the balance of considerations may
come out differently in different areas within patent, copyright, and trademark
law. Some differentiation can be accommodated within existing doctrinal
frameworks simply by providing an alternative route for earlier claiming in cases
where the chase is costly or protracted, as with trademark intent-to-use
applications and copyright preregistration. But, subject to concerns about
administrability and any costs of diminished standardization, the law should
probably go further. It is unclear, for instance, that a first-to-file rule is superior
to first-to-invent across all patent types as a matter of first best.
243
In contexts
like pharmaceuticals with high upfront development costs, earlier claiming
should be offered. Conversely, in areas where the danger of squatting or
misallocation is especially significant—as is likely the case with many business
method patents for instance—the award of rights should generally be delayed.
Admittedly, courts generally cannot simply propound different doctrines for
different subject-matters within the same branch of IP law. Often, such changes
can only be brought about legislatively. But this discussion of the treatment of
possession questions both for physical and intellectual property suggests there
is room for courts to consider ways in which the claiming of IP rights can be
more closely tailored to incorporate the concerns identified here. When the
USPTO or a trial court evaluates whether a patent satisfies the utility
requirement, for instance, the cost of developing the type of invention at issue is
an appropriate consideration. Insofar as the utility requirement shapes the nature
of possession in patent law, it should reflect the underlying nature of possession
rules and tilt toward later awards of rights when the costs of developing a
technology are low and earlier awards of rights when the cost of developing a
technology are high.
C. Theoretical Implications
1. On Defining IP Goods
This discussion of claiming rules is, for the most part, absolute. We assumed
that there was one clear rule for the “capture” of IP rights and, by extension, a
relatively clear sense of when the chase was underway that would culminate in
capture. This intuition stems from our physical property antecedents. Whatever
room for debate there may be at the margins, it is fairly obvious when a person
does and does not succeed in capturing a fox. We certainly have a pretty good
idea what a fox is, and a good intuition about what it means to actually capture
a fox versus merely to chase it. But IP law helps us see that these notions can be
situated within a wider continuum of development. What ultimately looks like
243
For these purposes, we set aside the benefits of international harmonization, which may
outweigh the value of any departure from a first-to-file regime.
454 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
actual capture, as opposed to simply some important step along the way, is a
function of how the legal system defines the thing to be captured. In IP law, the
nature of the thing itself is not given but is a creature of law. The result is both
greater uncertainty and greater flexibility.
244
Intellectual property shows that the
terms “committed search” or “actual capture” are not inevitable names for
concrete moments in a resource’s chase chronology, but rather mere names for
early or late points in time along that chronology, and that it is possible for the
legal system to work with more than just two points along this continuum.
For example, since 1976, a creative work has been protected by federal
copyright law as soon as it is fixed in a physical copy and need not also be
published, as prior federal copyright statutes required.
245
If we think of the
Copyright Act as a system that protects physical embodiments of completed
works, using fixation to define possession looks like a rule of capture. If,
however, we think of federal copyright law as a system centered on publication,
granting copyrights based on fixation looks less like a rule of capture and more
like a first-committed-searcher rule. In trademark law, similarly, use in
commerce looks like a rule of capture if trademark law is conceived as simply
the creation of a brand name, but it looks like a first-committed-searcher rule if
we think the ultimate object of trademark law is a successful, well known, and
highly valued mark, like the famous marks protected against dilution.
In IP law, more is up for grabs than with physical property. The “things” of
IP law used to organize IP rights are more variable than those of physical
property.
246
This is part of what compounds the difficulties of notice and clear
conceptual thinking in intellectual property, which can be ameliorated somewhat
through devices like rights registries. But it also provides for greater flexibility
and tailoring, helping to facilitate the sometimes sliding-scale quality of IP
protection. Trademarks receive some protection upon the registration of mere
intent to use. Then greater protection is given after use in commerce is shown
and, where required, the acquisition of secondary meaning, but more protection
244
Cf. Coll. Sav. Bank v. Fla. Prepaid Postsecondary Educ. Expense Bd., 527 U.S. 666,
675 (1999) (considering but rejecting various candidates for “property” created by Lanham
Act false advertising provisions).
245
See 17 U.S.C. § 302(a) (creating copyright in work at time of creation). Common law
principles offered some protection for unpublished works under state law. See Stanley v.
Columbia Broad. Sys., Inc., 221 P.2d 73, 78 (Cal. 1950) (en banc) (“[C]ommon law prohibits
any kind of unauthorized interference with, or use of, an unpublished work on the ground of
an exclusive property right, and the common-law right . . . exist[s] until lost or terminated by
the voluntary act of the owner . . . .”).
246
See Henry E. Smith, Intellectual Property as Property: Delineating Entitlements in
Information, 116 Y
ALE L.J. 1742, 1755 (2007) (“‘Invention space’ and original expressions
do not come pre-carved into things. That is, we are implicitly treating an invention as a thing
when the interest in its use—the various activities—are described at a high level of generality
not tied directly to the activity itself.”).
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 455
if they are “strong” and still more if they are “famous.”
247
Copyright functions
more obviously like a system of temporal priority for works that are widely
circulated since copying is more easily shown when a work is well known.
248
Patent law, too, has doctrines that afford greater protection to inventions that are
more developed. For instance, while commercialization is not required for a
patent to issue, commercial success is an important factor in analyzing whether
a patent satisfies the all-important requirement of non-obviousness.
249
Likewise,
pioneer patents generally receive stronger protection than those covering
improvements.
250
In the final analysis, IP law itself can be characterized as a kind of first-
committed-searcher rule writ large, at least where the rights at issue are
understood as essentially commercial in character. Patents and copyrights grant
inventors and authors a head start over others in capturing market share and
building customer goodwill. This is no small thing—indeed, it is one of the
ironies of IP law that a patent-holder’s commercial success can be so complete
that it results in the destruction of its trademark rights by causing the patent-
holder’s trademark to become generic.
251
And trademark law itself even more
clearly aligns with this conception of intellectual property as a kind of limited
protection in the process of acquiring property through actual commercial
exchange. Trademark law requires active use of a mark,
252
renewal of
registration,
253
and the ongoing payment of fees.
254
Though trademark law is not
247
See, e.g., AMF, Inc., v. Sleekcraft Boats, 599 F.2d 341, 349 (9th Cir. 1979) (setting
forth test for trademark infringement in which infringement depends, inter alia, on strength of
mark).
248
See supra notes 163-67 and accompanying text (describing trademark dilution
protection requiring widespread brand recognition).
249
See Graham v. John Deere Co., 383 U.S. 1, 17-18 (1966) (noting commercial success
as “indicia of obviousness or nonobviousness”); MPEP § 2141(II) (9th ed. Rev. 3, Jan. 2018)
(noting that examiners should consider secondary considerations put forth in Graham v. John
Deere including “commercial success, long felt but unsolved needs, [and] failure of others”).
250
See Wright Co. v. Herring-Curtiss Co., 211 F. 654, 655 (2d Cir. 1914) (endorsing Judge
Learned Hand’s lower court reasoning giving liberal interpretation for pioneering inventions).
251
See, e.g., Murphy Door Bed Co. v. Interior Sleep Sys., Inc., 874 F.2d 95, 97 (2d Cir.
1989) (“We hold that ‘Murphy bed’ is a generic term, having been appropriated by the public
to designate generally a type of bed. Consequently, defendants could not have infringed on
plaintiff’s trademark alleged to be Murphy bed . . . .”).
252
Abandonment is presumed after three years of non-use. See Lanham Act § 45, 15
U.S.C. § 1127 (2012).
253
See id. § 1059(a) (“[E]ach registration may be renewed for periods of 10 years at the
end of each successive 10-year period following the date of registration upon payment of the
prescribed fee and the filing of a written application, in such form as may be prescribed by
the Director.”).
254
See id.; U.S. PATENT & TRADEMARK OFFICE, FEE SCHEDULE (2018),
https://www.uspto.gov/learning-and-resources/fees-and-payment/uspto-fee-
456 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
subject to fixed terms of duration in the manner of patent and copyright law, it
is even more clearly limited by a kind of hot pursuit requirement. Its origins in
unfair competition law illustrate its core purpose—to secure to a firm that has
managed to establish goodwill in the mind of a consumer an exclusive right to
capitalize upon it, in a quest for the ultimate good to be captured: the consumer’s
business.
255
2. Divided Possession Rules
The first possession discussion in the literature has often been conducted
under an implicit assumption that largely identical pursuers will race to own a
resource, and that the only task left for the law is to determine the optimal timing
of possession. While true in many contexts, sometimes efficiency dictates the
division of labor among two or more pursuers, where each is uniquely positioned
to conduct one crucial phase in the resource’s hunt or development. In such
cases, a different type of original acquisition rule might be called for, one which
would coordinate the actions of several unrelated pursuers, incentivizing each to
conduct one crucial step along the pursuit’s chronology.
Indeed, Ellickson’s seminal treatment of whalers’ norms discusses, if at lesser
extent, a rule of this sort in fisheries where the value of a whale’s carcass would
be “split between the first harpooner and the ultimate seizer,” in some cases on
a fifty/fifty basis. The efficiency rationale suggested to support this rule was one
of division of labor: this rule would incentivize the first harpooner to meet a
school of whales (characteristic to those fisheries) to focus on striking as many
of them as quickly as possible before they dissipated, while, at the same time,
incentivizing other whalers to chase and capture the many dissipating
encumbered whales.
256
This rule would arguably result in a greater yield than
either the first-committed-searcher rule or the rule of capture, which would focus
the first whaler’s attention on completing the hunt of one whale at a time, start
to finish.
The possiblity of divided awards is not foreign to IP law. Most notably, the
notion of “blocking patents” in patent law can be thought of as splitting rights
over a larger inventive space between a first-generation inventor and a follow-
on improver. Each obtains a right to control aspects of the improved invention,
such that both need to come to terms in order for the improvement to be used.
The doctrine incentivizes each to perform important tasks in the invention
schedule#TM%20Process%20Fee [https://perma.cc/P4TW-XHLZ] (defining various fees for
trademark processing at the USPTO, including trademark renewal fees).
255
See McKenna, supra note 168, at 1840-41 (“[T]rademark law was not traditionally
intended to protect consumers. Instead, trademark law, like all unfair competition law, sought
to protect producers from illegitimate diversions of their trade by competitors.”).
256
See Ellickson, supra note 45, at 92-93.
2019] RIGHT ON TIME 457
chronology that they are uniquely capable of performing.
257
Abstracting away
from particular detail, property and IP doctrine can form original acquisition
rules that create entitlements, which are in some sense shared among several
parties in ways that induce them to move cooperatively along the chronology of
a resource’s pursuit and development.
One may wonder why explicit reliance on divided entitlements is not
undertaken more widely in IP law. Part of the reason may have to do with the
difficulty of obtaining the information needed to assess relative contributions of
different parties and their unique capabilities in various settings. One can also
view patent and copyright laws’ limited duration—a feature absent from
common-law property—as a primary mechanism to coordinate between
different generations of authors and inventors, incentivizing each to come forth
with their unique contributions to the advancement of the arts and sciences.
C
ONCLUSION
Long before the legal academy became interested in whaling norms, Herman
Melville took up the subject of first possession, devoting an entire chapter of
Moby-Dick to the fast-fish/loose-fish doctrine.
258
The world, Melville
concluded, is full of fast-fish—of people and places captured and controlled by
others. Yet, he continued, even more plentiful are the world’s loose fish—all
those materials as yet free but available for the taking by whomever can capture
them first. He asked, “What are men’s minds and opinions but Loose-Fish?”
259
“What is the great globe itself but a Loose-Fish? And what are you, reader, but
a Loose-Fish and a Fast-Fish, too?”
260
Ultimately, possession is not about mere law any more than Moby-Dick is
about mere whales, especially when it comes to intellectual property. Once a
relatively obscure set of fairly technical disciplines, Intellectual property has
proliferated over the last century to occupy a central position in the law, both
within the United States and globally. Its domain is human ingenuity and the
substratum of much contemporary life—technology, communication,
entertainment, and commerce. What chunks of these are free for capture, and
what it takes to capture them, are critical in determining the direction and
composition of society. These grand themes, however, still depend on the
particulars of legal doctrine and the conceptual framework that shapes and is
shaped by them. The sound development of intellectual property’s possessory
doctrines requires careful attention to detail and a systematic understanding of
257
See Robert Merges, Intellectual Property Rights and Bargaining Breakdown: The Case
of Blocking Patents, 62 TENN. L. REV. 75, 81 (1994) (“Blocking patents thus represent an
interesting property rights institution that balances incentives for pioneers with incentives for
independent inventors to push pioneering technology forward.”).
258
See MELVILLE, supra note 46, at 329.
259
Id. at 1219.
260
Id.
458 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 99:395
the considerations that are at play. Simply put, we cannot get it right if we do
not understand what is going on.
This Article set forth an account of the central features that drive first
possession in the law, describing both the forms first possession rules take and
the functions different approaches perform. IP law is subject to the same basic
set of trade-offs that shape traditional first possession doctrines—particularly
the danger of failure to complete the chase, on the one hand, and the risk of
wasteful duplication and reluctance to compete due to fear of lost investments,
on the other. At the same time, however, the balance between these concerns
differs in important respects, as do the institutional possibilities IP law affords.
Intellectual property faces particularly acute problems of asymmetric
information, but it also allows for greater flexibility through the use of
centralized registries and a wider array of possibilities in defining the “things”
that can be protected. In some ways, the law sensibly responds to these
differences between the tangible and the intangible, but often imperfectly and
without a clear understanding of the underlying stakes. By confronting these
issues in a systematic and integrated way, this Article set out a useful platform
from which to survey the wider horizon of intellectual property and better chart
the course that lies ahead. The need for a clear grasp of the fundamentals will
prove critical in the decades to come, for intellectual property is still in its
relative infancy and if, as Melville might say, it is in some respects a fast-fish,
but in others it is very much a loose-fish too.