Jewish Thought
Journal of the
Goldstein-Goren International Center for Jewish
Thought
Editors
Michal Bar-Asher Siegal Jonatan Meir Shalom Sadik
Howard Kreisel (editor-in-chief)
Guest Editors
Avriel Bar-Levav Oded Ysraeli
Editorial Secretary
Asher Binyamin
Volume 3
Asceticism in Judaism and the Abrahamic Religions
Beer-Sheva, 2021
Table of Contents
English Section
7
Foreward
9
Sexual Desire in the Book of the
Watchers (1 Enoch 6-36) and the
New Testament Exhortation to
Sexual Abstinence
Rivka Nir
35
Karaite Mourning of Zion as an
Ascetic Movement
Daniel J. Lasker
49
Returning Every Good to the
Lord: The Ascetic Exemplarity of
Francis of Assisi
Krijn Pansters
67
Asceticism among the Judeo-
Sufis of Egypt: The Cases of R.
Abraham Maimonides and R.
David II Maimonides
Paul B. Fenton
99
Ascetic Eating Practices and
Torah Study in the Pesaqim of R.
Moses of Evreux and His Circle
Ephraim Kanarfogel
115
The Ambiguous Attitude to
Asceticism in Medieval Jewish
Philosophy and the Case of Levi
ben Avraham
Howard Kreisel
137
Potencies of the Body and Soul:
Ascetic Ideals and Ritualistic
Meals in the Writings of R.
Baḥya ben Asher
Adam Afterman and
Idan Pinto
181
Otherness Precedes Asceticism:
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of
Onto-theology
Stavros Panayiotou
221
Contributors
Hebrew Section
7
Foreword
9
The Affliction of Minors on Yom
Kippur
Rabin Shushtri
40
Some Remarks on Medieval
Jewish Rationalism's Extreme
Asceticism
Dov Schwartz
60
Preaching, Art and Ascetism in
the Italian Renaissance
Nirit Ben-Aryeh Debby
82
The Way of Piety of Don Isaac
Abarbanel
David Ben Zazon
100
“To be Strangers in Your Land”:
Israel as an Ascetic Space in Early
Modern Ashkenazi Culture
Avraham Oriah
Kelman
134
Asceticism, Sexuality and Torah
Study in Slonim Hasidism
Noga Baror-Bing
158
Contributors
Otherness Precedes Asceticism:
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
1
Stavros Panayiotou
St. Kliment Ohridski University
ABSTRACT
In this paper, I explore Emmanuel Levinas’s ethical dialectic on asceticism
and its relation to otherness and closeness. In parallel, I argue that Levinas’s
stance on asceticism constitutes a vehement criticism of the analytic
insistence on onto-theology. In Levinas’s later works, particularly Otherwise
than Being or Beyond Essence, he maintains that Christian asceticism (especially
in the Orthodox and Protestant traditions) has mistakenly focused on onto-
theology, i.e., on an incarnated God who comes to mind. On the one hand, a
number of continental thinkers argue that an individual can achieve direct
communication with God through a symmetrical, reciprocal relation as a
self-contained unit. Kierkegaard, for instance, claims that the subject’s
isolation through asceticism is a necessary and sufficient condition to meet
God. As each person is responsible directly to God and his responsibility is a
matter of his faith, the religious life does not coincide with ethics and
sometimes even appears as an absurdity if measured by ethical norms.
Similarly, Heidegger endorses the radical replacement of religion,
prioritizing consciousness and cognition as necessary and sufficient
conditions to comprehend God, via the esotericism of Dasein. Levinas raises
severe objections to these positions. He claims that God exists outside of the
cosmos and that we can seek only His trace through the other person. Hence,
an individual cannot be in a direct relation with God as the person is a finite
being and God is Transcendence (Infinity). This is why God disappears from
human relations after sending the Other to me and subjugating me as a
hostage. It is only here that we can speak about asceticism, that is, the
individual must appear only as an equal interlocutor, as a subject, not as an
object, emptying itself and abandoning all its ontological narcissistic criteria
for the Other. In this sense, the ascetic self always starts from the Other.
However, Levinas goes further, arguing that God leaves all human affairs in
our own hands, absenting Himself almost entirely from our world. To
1 I would like to express my gratitude to Prof. M. Dimitrova (University of Sofia)
and Dr. A. Georgallides (University of Cyprus) for their wise guidance, advice,
and productive feedback on a previous draft of this article. They both
immensely improved the argumentation and methodology of this text.
Jewish Thought
3 (2021): 181-220
Levinas, the individual is a subject in the sense of being commanded by and
thus subject to God. One’s thinking and consciousness is awakened not by
exploiting the face of the Other but by serving it eternally as an infinite call
and response, as a substitute for a direct relationship with the Divine. One’s
self-conscious personality, the “I,” is secondary to the morally subjected
“me” which practices asceticism for the sake of the Other.
Introduction
“...moi responsable je ne finis pas de me
vider de moi-même”
2
The question of asceticism as a matter of consciousness begins with
Plato, who argued that a utilitarian process of goodness must be
distinguished from the absolute Good.
3
Plato, the first Theologian, as
a number of analytic thinkers characterized him, was the first
philosopher to systematically address asceticism and the Good in
terms of morality.
4
In medieval Byzantine
5
philosophy, in the Patristic
(Eastern) tradition, Christian Fathers strove to isolate the subject to
achieve kenosisby following a path that recognized only the self and
the spirit of God as necessary and sufficient conditions of the soul’s
salvation.
6
This line of thought has been further explored in the
2 E. Levinas, De Dieu qui vient à l’idée (Paris: Librarie Philosophique, 1986), 120;
trans. B. Bergo, Of God Who Comes to Mind (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1998), 73: “…as a responsible I, I never finish emptying myself of myself.”
3 See H.L. Stewart, “Was Plato an Ascetic?,The Philosophical Review 24.6 (1915):
603-13.
4 It is worth mentioning that Levinas was a great admirer of Plato, and summed
up his view of Plato’s contributions to philosophy, theology, and ethics in his
remark that “philosophy is Platonic.” See E. Levinas, Alterity and Transcendence,
trans. M.B. Smith (New York: Columbia University Press, 1999), ix. See also his
comments on Plato in Levinas, Collected Philosophical Papers, trans. A. Lingis
(Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1987), 23.
5 Levinas seems to have been familiar with Byzantine theological tradition. In his
work Time and the Other, trans. R.A. Cohen (Pittsburg: Duquesne University
Press, 1987), 70, n. 43, he discusses Heidegger’s view on death in relation to
Byzantine tradition: “Death in Heidegger is not, as Jean Wahl says, the
impossibility of possibility, but the possibility of impossibility. This apparently
Byzantine distinction has a fundamental importance.”
6 By Patristic tradition, we mean the Christian Orthodox perspective in which
self-transcendence depends on Trinitarianism through kenosis and faith. This
thesis sets up an intriguing opposition between the Orthodox conception of
human and divine personhood as being grounded in love and the relationship
to the other, on the one hand, and conceptions of personhood drawn from post-
Stavros Panayiotou
Cartesian philosophy, emphasizing such attributes as rationality and self-
consciousness, on the other. criterialism: Concerning the theory of criterialism
see T. S-G. Chappell, “Knowledge of Persons,” European Journal for Philosophy of
Religion 5.4 (2013): 31-56. Fr Sophrony of Essex, one of the major defenders of
Patristic tradition, insists that God is not a mere essence or an Absolute Being
without direct characteristics. On the contrary, he reminds us that God says:
γ εμι ν(I am who I am) (Exodus 3:14), and demonstrates that God is a
person and human beings need the same personal adjustment to be called
persons. Sophrony insists that if we want to justify personhood we must turn
towards the Triune God, the real and perfect personal existence. Sophrony
posits an absolute correlation and symmetry between God and Man, as in
Kierkegaard. Although God is uncreated and Man is created, it is possible to
share the same personal measures, thus enabling an entity to become a person
exactly as it happens to the Triune God. Levinas, on the other hand, would
reject this argument, since, in Judaism God does not become a person, and there
is no becoming in God, especially not the essential becoming described by
Sophrony. Thus, for Levinas, God cannot become a person in the same way
humans do, because there is no way that God has become a person (or three
persons into one substance, as held by Christian Trinitarianism). Levinas takes
a clear stand in the debate on incarnation, vehemently rejecting any theories
that could objectify God’s essence. For Levinas, everything is about Ethics, and
whether Man can realize and understand his power to ethical consent, namely,
to seek the trace of God through the face of the other person. Levinas
understands kenosis only through man’s capabilities and not through God’s
direct interference in the world (as Orthodox Christians do). For Levinas, “more
important than God's omnipotence is the subordination of that power to man's
ethical consent. And that, too, is one of the primordial meanings of kenosis.” See
E. Levinas, “The Name of God According to a Few Talmudic Texts,” in Beyond the
Verse: Talmudic Readings and Lectures, trans. G.D. Mole (Bloomington: The
Athlone Press, 1994), 126. The most valuable and comprehensive works
concerning asceticism as kenosis in (medieval) Patristic tradition is N.V.
Sakharov, I Love Therefore I am: the Theological Legacy of Archimandrite Sophrony
(2002): 93-115. See also J-C Larchet, “Suffering in Spiritual Life and Teaching of
Elder Sophrony (in Greek),” Πρακτικά Διορθόδοξου Επιστημονικού Συνεδρίου:
Γέροντας Σωφρόνιος. Ο Θεολόγος του Ακτίστου Φωτός (2007): 435-56; see
especially the English summary: 455-56. A comparative study between Levinas
and Orthodox Patristic tradition on the relation of beings and freedom has been
published by T.A. Ables, “On the Very Idea of an Ontology of Communion:
Being, Relation and Freedom in Zizioulas and Levinas,” The Heythrop Journal 52
(2011): 672-83, especially chapter 2: “The Levinasian Critique of Ontology,” 676-
78. For Levinas’s view on ascetic suffering, see his chapter “Useless Suffering,”
in Entre Nous: On Thinking-of-the-Other, trans. M.B. Smith and B. Harshav (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1998), 91-102; and W. Edelglass, “Levinas on
Suffering and Compassion,” Sophia 45.2 (2006): 43-59, where the author
discusses suffering along with being and alterity. See also a valuable text on
Levinas and kenosis written by R.D.N. van Riessen, Man as a Place of God: Levinas’
Hermeneutics of Kenosis (The Netherlands: Springer, 2007), especially Part II:
“Ethics, Religion and Kenosis,” 101-206, where the author defines and discusses
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
Western philosophical and theological tradition through the writings
of Augustine and Thomas Aquinas, where the subject must be seen as
a self-enclosed unit before God: asceticism of the spirit. We suggest
that for the Thomistic tradition, asceticism precedes otherness and
individualism precedes relationalism, something that begins through
the strict esotericism of God’s essence and His relation to human
beings.
It is worth noting that the definition of esotericism, which has
then been translated as kenosis (asceticism), can be traced back to
Thomas Aquinas, in his works Summa Theologica
7
and Contra Errores
Graecorum,
8
where he claims that God’s mind is absolutely outside of
the cosmos and has nothing to do with our intentionality. God
provides a rather ascetic esotericism on how He explores His relation
to human beings. In other words, for Aquinas, God has no real
communication with nor relation to human beings, as He can neither
exceed His essence nor be compared to anything. God thus
communicates and relates to human beings only through an inner
esoteric dialogue
9
with Himself, in a process called by Aquinas
“esoteric asceticism.” Hence, the God-Man relationship is real from
the side of human beings but an illusion from that of God. However,
according to Aquinas (and centuries later through the Hegelian
dialectic), God’s spirit is translated (and there is only one way to be
translated) through the human being’s consciousness, due to the fact
the paramount importance of kenosis in Levinasian thought through Ethics and
Religion in comparison to other philosophical and theological accounts. The
terms “kenosis” and “self-emptying” sometimes also refer to the God-person
relation. For a helpful discussion on this matter, see M.L. Baird, “Whose Kenosis?
An Analysis of Levinas, Derrida, and Vattimo on God’s Self-Emptying and the
Secularization of the West,The Heythrop Journal 48 (2007): 423-37. As Baird
correctly points out (p. 424), “Levinas’s model of kenosis [which he defines,
borrowing Levinas’s phrase, ‘as subordination [of God’s omnipotence] to man’s
ethical consent;’ see E. Levinas, In the Time of the Nations, trans. M.B. Smith
(Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1994), 126] is a diachronic and
transcendental self-emptying that has no immediate real time analogue.”
7 St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 5 vols., trans. Fathers of the English
Dominican Province (Indianapolis: Christian Classics, 1981).
8 Concerning the analysis of Aquinas’s monograph see M. Jordan, “Theological
Exegesis and Aquinas's Treatise Against the Greeks,Church History 56.4 (1987):
445-456.
9 Concerning Levinas’s view on dialogue, divine and cosmic, see H. Ben-Pazi,
“Ethics Responsibility and Dialogue: The Meaning of Dialogue in Levinas’s
Philosophy,” Journal of Philosophy of Education 50.4 (2015): 1-20.
Stavros Panayiotou
that God cannot escape His necessity or His absolute essence.
Whatever enters a human being’s intentionality is solely through the
Spirit of God; our spirit derives and recalls ideas from God’s Spirit.
This is the only way, according to Aquinas and Hegel, for God to enter
humanity.
The aforementioned syllogism introduced by Aquinas is not far
from the contemporary Western tradition, as regards the analysis of
subjectivity in the fields of history and political philosophy. For
instance, a pessimistic line of thought runs that politics nowadays
(especially under socialism and capitalism) react exactly as the
Thomistic dialectic suggests: modern states develop a similar model
of thinking, that is, conventions, regulations, terms and conditions to
decide what is right and wrong, constructed and determined via
states’ esotericism. Modern states seek self-vindication through their
inner narcissistic esotericism, which is possible to trace back to
Aquinas’s onto-theological theory.
To return to our main discussion, Levinas is not far from the
above tradition, which is quite anti-Christian.
10
Philosophically
speaking, he follows the same path as those who reject deism and hold
that God does exist infinitely and beyond metaphysics, above any
secular onto-theological knowledge and apprehension.
11
In parallel,
he would agree with Aquinas that even though God exists, He cannot
exceed His essence and His Absolute necessity, and thus cannot
possibly interact directly with human beings, as Christians mistakenly
believe, through the appearance of a Man-God incarnate.
12
However,
Levinas takes the argument a step further. He maintains that the
Thomistic tradition of kenosis (i.e., inner esotericism of Spirit)
demands further clarification and modification. Crucially, Levinas
states that, “human existence should not be thought of as self-
10 By anti-Christian, I mean that, for Levinas, the incarnation of Logos cannot be
construed philosophically.
11 H. Ben-Pazi correctly maintains that the Levinasian perspective must be seen
primarily ethico-philosophically, through Jewish tradition, and not onto-
theologically, through the cosmic chain of immanence. He claims that “Levinas
offers a philosophical-ethical reading of Jewish wisdom, which gives religion
metaphysical meaning, but maintains its connection to normative ethical
discourse.” See especially H. Ben-Pazi, “Theodicy as the Justified Demands of
Atheism: Yeshayahu Leibowitz Versus Emmanuel Levinas,” Modern Judaism: A
Journal of Jewish Ideas and Experience 36.3 (2016): 266.
12 Concerning Levinas’s argumentation on the Christian principle of incarnation
of Logos, see Levinas, Entre Nous: On Thinking-of-the-Other, 53-60.
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
orientated, but as a reception of the other.”
13
This otherness, in turn,
precedes any asceticism. In this approach, the self must be exterior to
any esoteric narcissism. It must be responsive, hostage, subjected to
otherness, self-emptying, dispossessed.
14
This is the Levinasian
explanation of asceticism, bearing no resemblance to Aquinas’s divine
esotericism, which directly affects self-consciousness and the history
of man in general. Moreover, Levinas, like Kierkegaard, criticizes the
established Church’s mistaken use of the term asceticism by
defending secularism as a cosmic ideology that exploits humans’ free
will.
Kierkegaard, therefore, in order to bolster his ressentiment
against the established Church, proposed a rational, ascetic way of
life, combining the aesthetics-ethics-religion triptych with a kind of
isolationism, where self-consciousness and individual perception are
necessary and sufficient conditions to meet God.
15
On the other hand,
Levinas, who was familiar with Kierkegaard’s existential accounts of
asceticism, unpacked a different dialectic: otherness precedes
asceticism and relationalism precedes individualism. Levinas argues
that what stimulates an individual’s subjectivity to God is not a
rational mind or a systematic apprehension of intentionality (i.e.,
fundamental ontology) but the face of the Other (i.e., ethical
metaphysics).
Levinasian Ethics and the Problem of Onto-Theology
It is worth investigating whether we can provide valid arguments or
a proper ethical intuition to answer the following question: can
conscious human beings be cognitively aware of God? Philosophical
accounts integrating God with man’s thinking appeared centuries
before Christ. Socrates (470-399 BC) and especially Plato (427-423 BC)
16
13 Van Riessen, Man as a Place of God: Levinas’ Hermeneutics of Kenosis, 1.
14 S. Benso clearly defines Levinas’s notion of asceticism by saying, “Levinas
maintains, the other is always a step beyond, always further than the I can
reach (the ascetic ideal!);” See S. Benso, “Levinas: Another Ascetic Priest?,
Journal of the British Society of Phenomenology 27.2 (1996): 142.
15 Concerning Kierkegaard’s notion of asceticism, see N. Khawaja, The Religion of
Existence: Asceticism in Philosophy from Kierkegaard to Sartre (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 2016), loc. 1601-2580 [Kindle version].
16 For instance, Plato, in his work Parmenides, denies any ontological relation
between God (τό ν) and logos. He contends in Parmenides’s dialogue that “[...]
οδαμς ρα στί τό ν. Ο φαίνεται […] τό v οτε στίν […] Οδ ρα
Stavros Panayiotou
together with Aristotle (382-322 BC)
17
systematized the philosophy of
religion during the fifth and fourth centuries BC. But it was Plotinus
(204/5-270 AD)
18
who having pre-Socratic influences first initiated
νομα στίν ατώ, οδέ λόγος, οδέ τις πιστήμη, οδέ ασθησις, οδέ δόξα.
[…] Οδέ νομάζεται, οδέ λέγεται, οδέ γιγνώσκεται.” See Plato, Λάχης,
Μένων, Παρμενίδης, (in Greek), tr. B. Τatakis, (Athens: Daidalos, 1990), 72: 142a.
(Trans.: The One cannot be shown. It is invisible, separated from the Being,
which should be neither named, nor described not thought of nor known.) For
the hypothesis of the Idea and Good in Plato, see J. Grondin, Introduction to
Metaphysics: from Parmenides to Levinas, trans. L. Soderstrom, (New York:
Columbia University Press, 2012), 21-45.
17 Concerning Aristotle’s Metaphysics, especially book E’, Z’, Λ’ and his
consideration of being as being and Being as first philosophy, see Grondin,
Introduction to Metaphysics, 46-55, and regarding onto-theology, see 55-66. For
Aristotelian Ethics, see Aristotle, (in Greek), vol. 1-4 (Thessaloniki: Zitros, 2006).
18 Concerning Plotinus’s Metaphysics of the One, see Grondin, Introduction to
Metaphysics, 68-73. In parallel, Levinas refers to Plotinus’s works several times.
Levinas is an admirer of Plotinus’s theological aspects especially concerning
Plotinus’s argument on “the One” (Τό ν). The majority of Medieval and
Byzantine philosophical and theological theories developed upon on the basis
of Plotinus’s and Neo-Platonists’ theology of the ν. The most comprehensive
monographies on Plotinus are written by H. J. Blumenthal, Soul and Intellect:
Studies on Plotinus and Later Neo-Platonism, 1993, especially ch. VI, 140-152, where
he comments on the Ennead V, which analyzes the notion of the One and what
it is to be intellectual. Also see J. Bussanich, “Plotinus’s Metaphysics of the One,
in L.P. Gerson (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1996), 38-65; and K. Corrigan, “Essence and Existence in the
Enneads”, 105-129 (both texts) in Gerson (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to
Plotinus, 1996. Levinas argues that “Plotinus conceived the procession from the
One as compromising neither the immutability nor the absolute separation of
the One. It is in this situation, at first purely dialectical and quasi-verbal […]
that the exceptional signifyingness of a trace delineates in the world” (Levinas,
Collected Philosophical Papers, 105-106). Presumably, Levinas derives several
ideas from Ennead V, where Plotinus explores his argument on the conception
of the One and his attributes against intelligibility, humans and absolute
knowledge. For instance, Levinas might agree with Plotinus’s position
regarding the Transcendence of the One: §6. [The One] is beyond being. This is
the requirement of negative theology. See Plotinus, The Enneads, ed. L.P. Gerson,
trans. G. Boys-Stones et al., (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018), 581.
However, Levinas would disagree with Plotinus’s generic remark that “the
Intelligibles are not outside the Intellect” (ibid. 5.5 [32], 583). Levinas argues
against this view since he believes that intelligibility is prior consciousness, will
and freedom. It dwells between me and the eternal a priori responsibility for the
Other. Levinas shows familiarity with Plotinus’s texts, saying, “if you read the
Enneads, the One doesn't even have consciousness of self, if it did have
consciousness of self, it would already be multiple, as a loss of perfection. In
knowledge, one is two, even when one is alone. Even when one assumes
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
the ‘duality of the One’ (τ ν ν δυσί ποστάσεσι), which influenced
a number of medieval thinkers such as Augustine (354-430 AD),
Maximus the Confessor (580-662 AD) Aquinas (1225-1274 AD), and
Anselm of Canterbury (1033-1109 AD), who brought questions about
God and philosophy of religion into metaphysics.
19
However, it was
Martin Heidegger who first introduced onto-theology, a term
unpacked in this chapter, into the philosophy of religion.
20
Specifically, this chapter analyses whether we can speak of God
beyond and above onto-theology. Before diving into arguments
regarding Levinas’s and Kierkegaard’s insights on God and our
subjectivity as a response to God’s command, several terms must be
defined.
By onto-theology,
21
we mean the integration of thinking
between beings qua beings and God. In short, onto-theology supports
the radical replacement of religion, giving priority to consciousness
and cognition as necessary and sufficient conditions to comprehend
God. In Kant’s words, “ontotheology describes a kind of theology that
aims to know something about the existence of God without recourse
to scriptural or natural revelation through mere concepts of reason
consciousness of self, there is already a split.” See Levinas, Entre Nous: On
Thinking-of-the-Other, 112.
19 Concerning the philosophy of religion from ancient times to the twentieth
century, see The History of Western Philosophy of Religion, 5 vols., ed. G. Oppy and
N.N. Tsakakis (London and New York: Routledge 2013).
20 Immanuel Kant coined the term “onto-theology,” but it was Heidegger who
introduced it to the context of the relation between theology and ontology.
Kant remarks that the belief that one can actually “strive for a supposed
contact with God” involves a “kind of madness.” See Kant, Religion within the
Boundaries of Mere Reason, trans. A. Wood and G. di Giovanni (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996), 16970. In parallel, Heidegger points out
that the onto-theological constitution of metaphysics brings God into
philosophy, leaving to be answered the question of how the deity enters into
philosophy. In Kantian thought, there is a return to onto-theology “in which it
determines the idea of God where God is posited as the totality of reality.” See
E. Levinas, God, Death and Time (California: Stanford University Press, 2000), 154.
21 One of the most “dangerous” pitfalls of onto-theology is the danger of
“reducing God to another familiar object of our worldly experience which is a
constant reality and threat in so much of theology and church life, often
exploding into public life in the form of fundamentalism.” See A.K. Min,
“Naming the Unnamable God: Levinas, Derrida and Marion,” International
Journal for Philosophy of Religion 60.3 (2006): 114.
Stavros Panayiotou
alone.”
22
By contrast, for Heidegger, “ontotheology is a critical term
used to describe a putatively problematic approach to metaphysical
theorizing”, something that, as Heidegger claims, “is characteristic of
Western philosophy in general.”
23
Influenced by Western tradition,
Heidegger “tries to turn existence into entities which can be
understood and mastered through technological drive.”
24
According
to Levinas, onto-theology “consists in thinking of God as a being and
in thinking being on the basis of this superior or supreme being.”
25
Levinas considers onto-theology as a misleading theory since it
“corrupts our thinking about God,” and thus we need to “think God
without Being.”
26
From the moment that God came into philosophy,
we can speak of onto-theology, in which world and being are always
“apprehended and comprehended by thinking.”
27
According to
Heidegger, “the comprehension of being in its truth was immediately
covered over by its function as the universal foundation of beings, by
a supreme being, a founder, by God. The thinking of being, being in its
truth, becomes knowledge (logos) or comprehension of God: theo-
logy.”
28
However, when “being is immediately approached in the form
of a foundation of beings, it comes to be named God”: this is onto-
theology.
29
The more thinking and logic are developed, the more we
22 See M. Halteman, “Ontotheology,” in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(London: Taylor and Francis, viewed 14 October 2019).
23 See S.R. Uttley, “‘Exorcising the Curse of Sisyphus’: English Catholic Education
and the Possibility of Authenticity: A philosophical Study after Heidegger,
Derrida, Lonergan and Boeve,” unpublished PhD thesis (Nottingham:
Nottingham Trent University, 2016).
24 See S. Minister. and J. Murtha, “Levinas and the Philosophy of Religion,
Philosophy Compass 5.11 (2010): 1029.
25 See Levinas, God, Death and Time, 160. Sometimes Levinas refers to God using
Platonic terminology: The Good/God. Levinas claims that “the Good is, in spite
of us” (M. Dimitrova, In Levinas’ Trace [Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars
Publishing, 2011], 42). By this statement he means that even if God exists, He
does not exist as most people think, but it is impossible to comprehend (as
beings) how God evaluates human situations and issues.
26 See note 16.
27 See, Levinas, God, Time and Death, 167.
28 Ibid., 123.
29 Ibid., 123. Several thinkers contend that Levinas does not intend to negate
Heidegger’s ontotheological insights entirely, but rather to recast them, since
he himself inserted God into conversation as well, albeit within an extremely
different framework: through the face-to-face relation. For instance, A.
Peperzak claims that Levinas has no intention to reject or to ‘destroy’
Heidegger’s thinking on ontotheology, but to criticize it as a “a manifestation
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
can speak of onto-theology. We can say that onto-theology is parallel
to fundamental ontology.
30
The image of God alone cannot be
construed without beings’ power of comprehension. People
throughout history did not have the power of comprehension because
they lacked technology, and only in modern times, with modern
technology, can they construe the image of God. Thus, onto-theology
needs a neo-technological culmination of modernism in order to
reveal itself. We can infer that, according to onto-theology, there is
no God without beings and no beings without God. God as Θεός, the
supreme infinite Being, is signified by beings, and beings are signified
by God. In western (Anglo-Saxon) philosophy of religion, onto-
theology is the mediator between God and beings (όντα) qua beings.
The Heideggerian being is an impersonal power leading “to an
account of history as impersonal destiny.”
31
The ethical stance of
Levinas “is not an instrumental contract that the self of will to power
[…] makes to defend itself against the other and to launch its self-
aggrandizing onslaught on the freedom of the other,”
32
but an infinite
command of goodness.
Meaning,
33
in onto-theology, does necessarily have to be.
Thought and comprehension are inseparable from meaning. To be
of the natural egoism which constitutes the elementary form of [immanent]
life.” See A. Peperzak, Beyond: The Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas (Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Press, 1997), 10.
30 By choosing this mode of thinking, that is, by considering God with the power
of knowledge and comprehension, we inevitably reduce God’s essence into
beings. This is a huge mistake, as God, according to Levinas, is irreducible to
human knowledge and Physics. R. Scruton, in support of this thesis, notes that
not only subjects but God is unrelated to objects and physical laws. It is only
objects that follow these laws. This is the reason why Levinas prefers the term
“humans” rather than “beings”: “Look for them [i.e. subjects] in the world of
objects and you will not find them. This is true of you and me; it is true too of
God. Physics gives a complete explanation of the world of objects, for that is
what “physics” means. God is not a hypothesis to be set beside the fundamental
constants and the laws of quantum dynamics. Look for him in the world of
objects and you will not find him.” See R. Scruton, The Face of God: The Gifford
Lectures (London: Continuum, 2012), 166. However, Levinas would have taken
this a step further, clarifying that not only cannot God be understood by the
laws of quantum physics, He cannot be understood directly by subjects either.
31
R. Kearney (ed.), Continental Philosophy in the 20th Century (London-New York:
Routledge [kindle paperback edition], 2003), loc. 4733.
32 Ibid. loc. 4905.
33 Levinas gives proper attention to meaning in his work Of God Who Comes to Mind,
trans. B. Bergo (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), 152-171.
Stavros Panayiotou
meaningful is a necessary and sufficient condition for being. That is,
being necessarily must confirm thought and knowledge. All these
characteristics of fundamental ontology imply that we cannot speak
of God outside the framework of onto-theology. However, ethical
philosophers raise several objections to the arguments discussed
above. For ethical thinking, in general, God must be understood (if we
ever can understand God) beyond onto-theology.
34
What is more,
according to Levinas, “it is from a certain ethical relationship that one
may start out on this search.”
35
Deriving from Plato’s view that
34 This is a very interesting point that requires further consideration. Even
Levinas, who vehemently rejects ontotheology, which gives priority to
rationality and teleology of reason (see D.F. Courtney, “The Teleology of
Freedom: The Structure of Moral Self-Consciousness in the Analytic,” in The
Teleology of Reason: A Study of the Structure of Kant's Critical Philosophy [Berlin: De
Gruyter, 2014], 248-291), “apologizes” to God and to himself because even
outside ontotheology, he attempts to speak about the Infinite (that is God) by
expressing his thoughts and insights, even if he provides ethical implications.
See Levinas, “The Temptation of Temptation,” in Nine Talmudic Readings, trans.
A. Aronowicz (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994), 30-50. For
instance, in Of God Who Comes to Mind, Levinas uses in the title the relative
pronoun who (who comes to mind). Thus, even if he wants to provide
arguments against ontotheology, he indirectly attributes human definitions to
God since the relative pronoun who is referring to humans: men and women. In
the second chapter of the above work he claims, “not to philosophize is still to
philosophize” (Of God Who Comes to Mind, 55). Even if Levinas clearly rejects
ontotheology by saying that the problem with ontotheology, that is finally a
kind of rational theology, is that “in thematizing God [and attributing Him
human conditions such as mind, voice, thinking, logic etc.] Theology has
brought Him into the course of being” (ibid.), he himself admits that he is
obliged by speech to express his opinion that there is no opinion about God.
However, he claims that in saying that there is no opinion about God we are
already expressing our opinion. This view is expressed by several thinkers who
claim that Ontotheology is inseparable to God-talk and God-discussion in order
to accept or raise questions about His essence and His relation to human beings.
For instance, J.W. Robbins alleges that we cannot escape Ontotheology even
though we do not accept it. Ontotheology together with the issue of death of
God cannot be overcome in no way since they are necessary and sufficient
condition for a possible God-talk. Inventing and using the term “God” in any
science, we automatically adopt ontotheology as a subsidiary factor for a God-
talk. “For, the endeavor at overcoming remains trapped within ontotheology,
and what is worse, it confuses this trap as the problem when in fact it is the
very clue needed for thinking otherwise.” See J.W. Robbins, Between Faith and
Thought: An Essay on the Ontotheological Condition (Charlottesville: University of
Virginia Press, 2003), 3.
35 See Levinas, God, Time and Death, 125.
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
“Good
36
[by which Levinas presumably means the divine supreme
God] is beyond being,” Levinas builds up the structure of his “radical
alterity.”
37
As he points out, there is an urgent need to distinguish
philosophy from theology, for “to philosophy belongs being and to
Theology there is faith, revelation and God.”
38
It is worth noting that even though this chapter analyses and
compares Levinas’s and Kierkegaard’s views regarding God, and how
beings are interrelated to God, we need to begin with Heidegger in
order to better understand the vital role of Sameness and Otherness.
Onto-theology gives priority to Sameness, tying logic to the relation
between God and people. Thinking of God starts from beings and
returns to the beings themselves. In this way, the Same presses the
Other to be absorbed and return to Sameness, all the while without
revealing itself. Thus, the Other depends on the Same, even while it is
addicted and integrated into the latter. The Other, according to onto-
theology, is trapped by the Same, unable to escape.
39
However,
according to Levinas, Otherness is a separate version of one’s self
which has never been adopted or absorbed by Sameness. In parallel,
only through one’s relation to the Other can one find God:
To be oneself is already to know the fault I have committed with
regard to the Other. But the fact that I do not quiz myself on the
Other's rights paradoxically indicates that the Other is not a new
edition of myself; in its Otherness it is situated in a dimension of
36 See below Levinas’s definition of Good: “The Good invests freedom - it loves me
before I love it. Love is love in this antecedence. The Good could not be the term
of a need susceptible of being satisfied, it is not the term of an erotic need, a
relationship with the seductive which resembles the Good to the point of being
indistinguishable from it, which is not its other, but its imitator. The Good as
the infinite has no other, not because it would be the whole, but because it is
Good and nothing escapes its goodness.” See E. Levinas, Otherwise Than Being, or,
Beyond Essence, trans. A. Lingis (The Netherlands: Springer, 1991), 187, n. 8.
37 See ibid., 16; J. W. Robbins, “The Problem of Ontotheology: Complicating the
Divine between Theology and Philosophy,The Heythrop Journal 48 (2002): 142.
38 See J. W. Robbins, “The Problem of Ontotheology,” 147. Even though Levinas
stops short of admitting that his work is theological, there are several
similarities between his work and Karl Barth’s “theology of language,
especially when he tries to explain the notion of the Saying. See Graham Ward,
Barth, Derrida and the Language of Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1995), 147-170.
39 See Kearney ed., Continental Philosophy in the 20th Century, loc. 4790.
Stavros Panayiotou
height, in the ideal, the Divine, and through my relation to the
Other, I am in touch with God.
(Levinas, Difficult Freedom: Essays on Judaism, 1)
Levinasian Prioritizing of Ethics as First Philosophy over Onto-
Theology
40
It is [for Levinas] a question of attaining, via the royal road of
ethics, the supreme being, the truly being […]. And this being is
man, determined as face in his essence as man on the basis of his
resemblance to God. Is this not what Heidegger has in mind when
he speaks of the unity of metaphysics, humanism and onto-
theology? […] ‘The Other resembles God.’ Man’s substantiality,
which permits him to be face, is thus founded in his resemblance
to God, who is therefore both the Face and absolute substantiality.
(J. Derrida, Writing and Difference, 142)
It is crucial to unpack the Levinasian notion of God outside the context
of onto-theology. Before discussing Levinas’s arguments concerning
God and His relation to human beings, we have to understand why he
considers ethics as first philosophy
41
and how we can approach the
relations among ethics, knowledge and philosophy of religion.
40 Several thinkers who study Levinas agree with this statement. Some of them,
however, instead of ethics, use Levinas’s phrase “Metaphysics precedes
Ontology” to explain the differences between Heideggerian ontology and
Levinasian ethics. See E. Levinas, Totality and Infinity, tr. A. Lingis (Pittsburg, PA:
Duquesne University Press, 1969), 42. For instance, J. Grondin maintains that,
mistakenly, “driven by its will to power and its egoism, ontology is transformed
into first philosophy”. He continues with the observation that Levinas, “in
order to combat [without infringing as Levinas’s intention is not to infringe
on or entirely skip over Heidegger’s ontology, but rather to put priorities
between ontology and metaphysical ethics] its ontological imperialism
proposes a terminological inversion: the primacy of the Same becomes that of
the other, and ontology’s primacy is transferred to ethics.” See Grondin,
Introduction to Metaphysics, 244. Here Grondin analyses metaphysics as ethics
and not as a science which investigates Being as Being nor as the fundamental
ontological event of our existence.
41 That is to say, “Being only discovers itself by its being called [and not by its will]
by the call [and not the will] of the other. Thus, before being comes
responsibility, which implies a more originary origin than being itself.” See
Robbins, “The Problem of Ontotheology,” 146.
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
Levinas, in his renowned article Ethics as First Philosophy,”
42
raises several objections against traditional classical knowledge,
explaining that there are various disadvantages to the ontological
basis behind knowledge which is explained by analytical thinkers
merely as experience and apprehension. The problem, as he points
out, is that the classical notion of knowledge starts from immanence:
“The ideal of rationality begins to appear as the immanence of the real
to reason.”
43
The problem Levinas observes can be traced to a
mistaken approach to freedom of knowledge which, according to
classical tradition, is essentially the inspiration for the mind where
(Hegelian) wisdom of first philosophy is reduced to spirit as self-
consciousness.”
44
“It is to be found in the concept of consciousness
with the interpretation of cogito given by Descartes,”
45
something that
has been described by Husserl as intentionality “consciousness of
something.”
46
Also, for Levinas, experience mistakenly expressed by
western analytical thought as “collective and religious experience.”
47
42 R. Kearney and M. Rainwater (eds.), The Continental Philosophy Reader (London
and New York: Routledge, 1996), 124-135.
43 Ibid.
44 G.L. Aronoff, Guilt, Persecution and Atonement: Moral Responsibility in Loewald and
Lévinas (unpublished PhD thesis, Concordia University Press, 2010), 148, n. 295.
45 See Kearney and Rainwater (eds.), Continental Philosophy Reader, 125. It is
important to consider briefly what is the main difference between Levinas and
Descartes regarding their views on God, as both affirm the existence of God but
within different metaphysical frameworks. Although Descartes admits that
there is a God who is absolute and infinite, he “employs causal and ontological
arguments to demonstrate that there is a God.” See R. Bernasconi and D. Wood
(eds.), The Provocation of Levinas: Rethinking the Other (London-New York:
Routledge, 1988), 139. Levinas, who agrees with Descartes on several points,
especially on the proposition that a subject has different thinking of his self and
different thinking of his finitude, as well as the belief that “infinitude is the
positive notion in terms of which the notion of man’s finitude is understood
(ibid., 142) underlines that one major difference with Descartes is that Levinas
does not care to provide ratiocinative arguments on what it is to be God because
we cannot say what God is at all. At this point I would like to express my sincere
gratitude to my supervisor, who patiently gave me specific directions on how I
can reflect Levinas’s terminology on God, illeity and transcendence, as well as
differentiating Levinas’s perspective on God from other thinkers who, while
admitting the existence of God, try to explain His existence with rational
exegesis, something that Levinas sees as absolute madness, maintaining that
we cannot compare or think of infinity with our finite mind.
46 R. Kearney and Rainwater (eds.), Continental Philosophy Reader, 125.
47 Ibid.
Stavros Panayiotou
Levinas argues that Husserl’s claims concerning intentionality
and self-consciousness are based on a faulty foundation.
48
According
to Husserl, “knowledge is a ‘filling out’ that gratifies a longing for the
being as object causing the world to be rediscovered as noema,”
49
where self-consciousness is a necessary and sufficient condition of
knowledge. As Husserl points out, “All acts generallyeven the acts
of feeling and will are ‘objectifying’ acts, original factors in the
‘constituting’ of objects, the necessary sources of different regions of
being and of the ontologies that belong therewith.”
50
For Levinas,
“reduced consciousness rediscovers and masters its own acts of
perception and science as objects affirming itself as self-
consciousness and remains a non-intentional consciousness of itself.”
51
48 Levinas agrees with the Husserlian dyadic relationship as a fundamental locus
of concern and responsibility. He also admits that his philosophical thinking on
the ‘Other’ derived from Husserl’s idea that “the Other is the condition of
correctness of my world and that each transcendence, including the
transcendence of the outer world, exists for me and is comprehensible to me
only by virtue of the transcendence of the Other.” However, for Husserl, “both
the Other and Transcendence are constituted in my immanence, whereas
Levinas refuses to consider the Other as my Alter Ego (See Dimitrova, In Levinas’
Trace, 19-20). The Other calls me, teaches me how to transcend my potential
into Infinity. Thus, I cannot escape responsibility and morality, which precede
both my freedom and my decisions against my neighbor. In parallel, a second
major problem with Husserlian phenomenology of the Other, as Levinas claims,
is that Husserl insists on the fact that the relation to the human Other be
understood as a relation of knowledge; in fact, Levinas argues, the Other can be
understood as a relation of being: “our intuitive grasp of the other depicts him
or her as a center of intentionality and hence as alter ego, as a sensuous-
conscious subject” (See H. Jodalen and J. Vetlesen [eds.], Closeness: An Ethics
[Oslo: Scandinavian University Press, 1997], 5). Levinas discusses Husserl’s view
on intentionality of consciousness and his method of Intuition by inferring that
they provide an overall evaluation of phenomenology: noesis-noemata are
revealed through the horizon of intentionality of consciousness, that is, the
latter is inseparable from the former. See E. Levinas, The Theory of Intuition in
Husserl’s Phenomenology, trans. A. Orianne (Illinois: Northwestern University
Press, 1995), 37-52 and 65-96. However, for Levinas, both terms lack an ethical
standpoint. Levinas argues that we need to take a step forward, from intuition
of essence to the philosophical intuition of existence: “Philosophical intuition
must not be more directly characterized without mentioning the
phenomenological reduction which introduces into the realm of
phenomenology” (ibid., 135).
49 Kearney and Rainwater (eds.), Continental Philosophy Reader, 127.
50 E. Husserl, Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, trans. W.R.B. Dixon
(London: George Allen and Unwin, 1931), section 117.
51 Kearney and Rainwater (eds), Continental Philosophy Reader, 127.
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
Thus, Levinas suggests “a consciousness of consciousness, indirect,
implicit and aimless without any initiative that might refer back to an
ego.”
52
Levinas also discusses another term, duration. By duration,
Levinas means “a consciousness that signifies not so much a
knowledge of oneself as something that effaces presence or make it
discreet.
53
This duration in phenomenological analysis remains “free
from the sway of the will,”
54
and the most crucial thing is that which
continues to be “absolutely outside all activity of the ego.”
55
Levinas thus initiates, in contrast to Husserl, not an ontological
but a transcendental phenomenology of the face where “the
proximity of the other is the face’s meaning” there is a “face to face
steadfast.”
56
In contrast to the classical notion of knowledge, Levinas
argues that (ethical) knowledge lies in the Other “prior to any
knowledge.”
57
The Other (l’Autre) thus presents itself as human Other (Autrui);
it shows a face and opens the dimension of height, that is to say,
it infinitely overflows the bounds of knowledge. Positively, this
means that the Other puts in question the freedom which
attempts to invest it; the Other lays himor herself bare to the
total negation of murder but forbids it through the original
language of his defenseless eyes
(Levinas, Transcendence and Height, 12).
52 Ibid., 127.
53 Ibid.
54 Ibid.
55 Ibid.
56 Ibid., 130. I would agree with Grondin’s claim that “the Other is always a face,
which can never be reduced to an idea I may have of it.” See Grondin,
Introduction to Metaphysics, 244-245. This statement can be justified if we look
carefully at Levinas’s phrase: “the way in which the other presents itself,
exceeding the idea of the Other in me, we here name face.” See Levinas, Totality
and Infinity, 50. For Levinas, in parallel, “the Other, Autrui, is not simply an alter
ego, an appresented analogue of myself. He and I are not equals, citizens in an
intelligible kingdom of ends…There is between us, an absolute difference. The
Other is he to whom and in virtue of whom I am subject, with a subjectivity that
is heteronomy, not autonomy, and hetero-affection, not auto-affection. The
Other is not the object of my concern and solicitude.” See Bernasconi and Wood
(eds.), The Provocation of Levinas, 140.
57 Kearney and Rainwater (eds.), Continental Philosophy Reader, 130.
Stavros Panayiotou
To answer another crucial question concerning the relation between
Christian ethics
58
and Levinas’s ethics, for Levinas, the Other becomes
my neighbor, not in the same manner as the Christian dictum ‘Love
your neighbor as yourself,’ but through a primordial concern about
the Other, that is, “the Other becomes my neighbor precisely through
the way the face summons me, calls for me, begs for me, and in so
doing recalls my responsibility and calls me into question.”
59
For
Levinas, responsibility exceeds the notion of Being as we know it in
the Heideggerian Being and Time, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit or in
other contemporary thinkers.
60
Being according to Levinas is of less
worth than people’s relations to each other. Responsibility is beyond
being and beyond being’s immanence.
Responsibility goes beyond being. In sincerity, in frankness, in
the veracity of this saying, in the uncoveredness of suffering,
being is altered. But this saying remains, in its activity, a
passivity, more passive than all passivity, for it is a sacrifice
58 Even though there are hundreds of discrepancies between Christian ethics and
Levinas’s ethics, Christian thought derives several principles and aspects from
Levinas’s thought. See specifically A. Peperzak, “The Significance of Levinas’s
Work for Christian Work,” in J. Bleochl (ed.), The Face of the Other and the Trace
of God: Essays on the Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas (New York: Fordham
University Press, 2000), 184-99. One of the most crucial discrepancies between
Levinas and Kierkegaard is the term kenosis, that is, abandoning everything and
everyone for the sake of the Other. This term is explored in particular by
Kierkegaard’s Christology. See D.R. Law, Kierkegaard’s Kenotic Christology
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013). 64-153.
59 Kearney and Rainwater (eds.), Continental Philosophy Reader, 131.
60 For instance, in Descartes the self is the I of the cogito (cogito ergo sum); the
center of consciousness leading to self-awareness and intentionality. In
Spinoza and several analytic philosophers, being is enriched by additional
emotions, desires, autonomy and freedom as well as second-order volitions,
something that it lacks in animals. In Hume, the character of beings is like a
container of ideas and expression that are expressed in language and self-
consciousness. With Husserl the being is embedded in the world within a
noematic-noetic framework explored as intentionality. In Heidegger this
embeddedness in the world is mainly practical and emotional, with being’s
attributes and conditions returning to itself. And finally, with Hegel, being is
totalized and thematized, taking its power and consciousness to its core and
depending on its interiority. With Hegel’s notion of the self, history ends.
“Hegel explicated the progress of reason in history that coincides with God’s
self-development toward absolute consciousness. Thus, for him, God becomes
Absolute Reason or Geist, the totality of reality.” See R. Urbano, “Approaching
the Divine: Levinas on God, Religion, Idolatry and Atheism,” Logos 15.1 (2012): 66.
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
without reserve, without holding back, and in this non-
voluntary the sacrifice of a hostage designated who has not
chosen himself to be hostage, but possibly elected by the Good,
in an involuntary election not assumed by the elected one.
(E. Levinas, Otherwise than Being, 15)
Despite the fact that Levinas agrees with Sartre’s expression of
“existence precedes essence,” he provides a different notion of freedom
61
and responsibility from that of Sartre’s “sincerity.
62
Levinas contends
that responsibility matters if and only if it goes beyond one’s
commitment to the Other, before being devoted to oneself, even
before being. In short, for Levinas, ethics precedes ontology,
63
and
61 According to Levinas, freedom is a characteristic that is misused, especially in
Western contemporary philosophy. By necessity it is related to human rights
and free will. If I have freedom, I am free to express my opinion without any
coercion. However, Levinas provides a different view on “Westernized”
freedom, which is relevant solely to reason and power: “In a civilization which
the philosophy of the same reflects, freedom is realized as a wealth. Reason,
which reduces the other, is appropriation and power” (Levinas, Collected
Philosophical Papers, 50).
62 Concerning similarities and discrepancies between Levinas and Sartre on God,
subjectivity and politics, see C. Howells, “Sartre and Levinas,” in Bernasconi
and Wood (eds.) The Provocation of Levinas, 91-99. The most profound
discrepancy between Levinas and Sartre is that the latter, in his work Being and
Nothingness, as an Atheist, prefers the Greek model of knowing, in which he
contends that the encounter between the I and the other person is an event of
cognition, where selfhood becomes another piece of “furniture” in a mere
procedure of intentional objects. See J-P Sartre, Being and Nothingness, trans.
H.E. Barnes (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956), 344-58). On the contrary,
Levinas, as a Jew, comes from the Biblical tradition where the Other is quite
relevant and important to ethical subjectivity of the pace of my life. The Other
appears as a “naked image” where she eternally seeks me to heal her wounds.
As G.L. Bruns correctly puts it, “for Levinas, the ethical subject is defined by a
responsibility that is prior to any rational deliberation executive decision; it is
an anarchic responsibility prior to the kind of commitments that rational
subjects […] know how to contract or refuse or hedge with loopholes and
provisos.” See G.L. Bruns., “On the Coherence of Hermeneutics and Ethics: An
Essay on Gadamer and Levinas,” in B. Krajewski (ed.), Gadamer's Repercussions:
Reconsidering Philosophical Hermeneutics (California: California University Press,
2004), 34.
63 As M. Ruti correctly states, “this [relational] way of envisioning subjectivity is
one reason that Levinasian phenomenology has played such a crucial role in
recent ethical theory, for Levinas sought to understand precisely what it means
to proceed from ethics to ontology rather than the other way around.” See M.
Stavros Panayiotou
transcendence
64
precedes immanence.
65
In contrast to Sartre,
responsibility for Levinas is “stemming from a time before my
freedom”.
66
It is the excellence of ethical proximity
67
before any
Ruti, Between Levinas and Lacan: Self, Other, Ethics (London and New York:
Bloomsbury, 2015), 2.
64 According to Levinas, “the transcendence of God is his actual effacement, but
this obligates us to men.” See W. Large, “The Name of God: Kripke, Levinas and
Rozenweig on Proper Names,” Journal of the British Society of Phenomenology 44.3
(2013): 331.
65 At this point, I raise objections to those who believe that there are two different
meanings of the Other in LevinasTotality and Infinity. For instance, Large insists
that immanence is related to transcendence, and that there would not have
been transcendence without first analyze immanence. And this is necessary
and sufficient condition to understand both God and human beings. See
William Large, “The Two Meanings of the Other in Lévinas Totality and Infinity,
Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 42 (2011): 243-254. Large claims
that “the other meaning, which is much less well-known, but which I believe is
its true meaning, is the Other of immanence and interiority” (ibid., 243).
Levinas, however, makes it clear in his work Entre Nous what he means by
asymmetrical relationship: “The relationship from me to the other is thus
asymmetrical, without noematic correlation of any thematizable presence. An
awakening to the other man, which is not knowledge” (Levinas, Entre Nous ,168).
Thus, from my point of view, immanence has nothing to do with ethical
transcendence, as the former is about rational beings and knowledge, and the
latter about infinite God. They cannot be related to or considered together.
Immanence, as an ontological term, deals with beings qua beings and
knowledge of beings. Transcendence, as an ethical term, deals with God. I agree
with A. Kin, who notes that for Levinas, “it is especially the encounter of a
particular kind of Other, the hungry, that shakes up our ordinary
ontotheological consciousness in its complacency, closure, and arrogance,
break the circle of immanence that imprisons us in mystification, deception,
and ideology, and open a break or fissure in the epic of being in the direction
of the beyond where another mode of transcendence can appear” (Kin 2006:
101). I would also agree with Grondin’s statement that for Levinas, all
ontological thought is one of immanence, of the same present in all individuals,
leveling over differences. But [on the other hand metaphysical [ethical]
thought is one that discovers the transcendence of the Other which exceeds all
my effort to understand it” (Grondin, Introduction to Metaphysics, 244).
66 Kearney and Rainwater (eds.), Continental Philosophy Reader, 131.
67 Proximity is a crucial term in Levinas’s thought. It is related to sensibility in
accordance with the matter of surprise. It has nothing to do with knowledge
and cognition since it strives to get to know the other not through experience
but mainly as a trace. Levinas states that sensibility “is itself exposed to alterity
[…] is the for-the-other of one's own materiality; it is the immediacy or the proximity
of the other […] a relation not of knowing but of proximity,” where the latter is
defined as an “anarchic relationship with a singularity without the mediation
of any principle, any ideality” (Levinas Otherwise Than Being, xxvi, 74, 100).
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
present. The most crucial and vital difference between Levinas and
Sartre (and the above Christian dictum) is that, for Levinas, “responsibility
for my neighbor dates from before my freedom in an immemorial past
[…] to which nothing in the rigorously ontological order binds me […]
an immemorial freedom that is even older than being.”
68
Though Levinas started his philosophical thought from
phenomenology, he abandoned the Husserlian observation of beings
that focused mainly on a metaphysical transcendence of what he calls
“Ethics as first philosophy”.
69
For Levinas, philosophy of the Other
echoes to infinity and the idea of the divine Other, whether or not this
Other is God or the other person. However, Levinas insists that we can
only see God and communicate with Him through his trace, that is,
the promise of openness to the other. R. Urbano correctly states that
for Levinas, “God is disclosed to man at the moment the person
responds to the call of the Other. This responsibility for the Other
attests to the presence of God.”
70
However, I would add that this
“presence” must be considered as indirect, since God’s presence is
impossible to our finite minds. “This is why the face, in contrast to
Hegel, is primordial and irreducible and it cannot be totalized, as the
infinite, i.e. God comes to epiphany there.”
71
What matters at all for
Levinas is not onto-theology but “the vulnerability of the eye of the
other,”
72
who commands you “Thou shalt not kill.”
The first word of the face is “Thou shalt not kill.” It is an order.
There is a commandment in the appearance of the face, as if a
master spoke to me. However, at the same time, the face of the
Other is destitute; it is the poor for whom I can do all and to
whom I owe all. And me, whoever I may be, but as a “first person
I am he who finds the resources to respond to the call.
(Levinas, Ethics and Infinity, 89)
Responsibility for the other the face signifying to me “thou
shalt not kill,” and consequently also you are responsible for the
life of this absolutely other is responsibility for the one and
68 Kearney and Rainwater (eds.), Continental Philosophy Reader, 131-32. For a study
of immense importance concerning the immemorial time, see Dimitrova, In
Levinas’ Trace, 37-48.
69 Kearney (ed.),
Continental Philosophy in the 20th Century, loc. 4718.
70 Urbano, “Approaching the Divine,” 59.
71 Kearney (ed.), Continental Philosophy in the 20th Century, loc. 4902.
72 Ibid., 4902.
Stavros Panayiotou
only. The one and only means the loved one, love being the
condition of the very possibility of uniqueness […] The alterity of
the other is the extreme point of the “thou shalt not kill” and, in
me, the fear of all the violence and usurpation that my existing,
despite the innocence of its intentions, risks committing.
(Levinas, Entre Nous, 168-169)
According to Levinas, “to separate God from onto-theology” is to
reexamine the notion of meaning.
73
As Levinas states (alongside
several postmodernist French thinkers such as Derrida
74
and Jean-Luc
Marion),
75
in order to escape from onto-theology and its quasi-
73 Levinas, God, Death and Time, 127.
74 Concerning similarities and discrepancies between Levinas and Derrida, see J.D.
Caputo, “Adieu-sans Dieu: Derrida and Levinas,” in Bloechl (ed.) The Face of the
Other and the Trace of God, 276-312. A variety of secondary literature is dedicated
to discussions on God, infinity, metaphysics and selfhood between Levinas and
Derrida (Baird, “Whose Kenosis?,” 423-37;
R. Bernasconi, “‘Only the Persecuted’:
Language of the Oppressor, Language of the Oppressed,” in A. Peperzak (ed.),
Ethics as First Philosophy: The Significance of Emmanuel Levinas for Philosophy,
Literature and Religion (London: Routledge, 1995), 77-86; idem, “Levinas and
Derrida: The Question of the Closure of Metaphysics,” in R.A. Cohen (ed.), Face
to Face with Levinas (New York: S.U.N.Y. Press, 1986), 181-202; D. Boothroyd, “Off
the Record: Levinas, Derrida and the Secret of Responsibility,” Theory Culture
and Society 28 (2011): 41-59; A.K. Min, “Naming the Unnamable God: Levinas,
Derrida and Marion,International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 60.3 (2006):
99-116;
M. Papastephanou, “Onto-Theology and the Incrimination of Ontology
in Levinas and Derrida,Philosophy and Social Criticism 31.4 (2005): 461-485; H.
Zaborowski, “On Freedom and Responsibility: Remarks on Sartre, Levinas and
Derrida,The Heythrop Journal 41 (2000): 147-165.
75 Derrida and Marion also raise several objections concerning the God of onto-
theology. For instance, Marion claims that “the God of ontotheology is only an
idol.” See J-L Marion, God Without Being: Hors-Texte, trans. T.A. Carlson (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1991); idem, The Idol and Distance: Five Studies, trans.
T.A. Carlson (New York: Fordham University Press, 2001). However, Marion
applied a different theoretical framework in discussing the philosophy of the
other and selfhood, criticizing Levinas that he did not escape from ontology (or
ontotheology) even if he provided an alternative to the phenomenology of
Husserl’s egology and Heidegger’s Ontotheology. On this issue, see C.M.
Gschwandtner, “The Neighbor and the Infinite: Marion and Levinas on the
Encounter between Self, Human Other, and God,” Continental Philosophical
Review 40 (2007): 231-249, esp. 233-37, where Marion expounds a vehement
critique of Levinas’s endeavor to destroy the self by giving absolute dominance
to the other. Gschwandtner on p. 234 cites Marion’s phrase that Levinas’s
“[insistent] sincerity phenomenologically destroys the terms of the ontological
difference,” imposing such a dramatic reduction of the Self that it is placed in
danger of elimination. For Marion, therefore, this “obedience to the ethical
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
immanent characteristics, we need to decenter the subject from
fundamental ontology and take into consideration “forms of thought
different from intentionality.
76
Levinas observes that “to think God
outside of onto-theology [is] to think no longer on the basis of
positivity.”
77
Otherness must be separated from Sameness so that the
former is not continuously absorbed by the latter. In this way, ethical
relationship is no longer subjugated by onto-theology or “from the
thinking of being”.
78
Levinas calls for reconsidering knowledge and
the manifestation of thinking beings. Unlike the Greeks, who
categorized knowledge within a tautological framework, Levinas
considers that meaning does not need manifestation of being; i.e. not
merely to be, but to become, since Levinas does not want to erase or
reject being (ontology), but he insists on giving priority to the ethical
term becoming, where the “I,” as subject, needs the Other to become.
Levinas raises objections to the onto-theological idea which
prioritizes a power of being that invites God to come to our minds
through logic and comprehension. Levinas opposes this concept with
a metaphysics of the good and the face-to-face intersubjective
relationship
79
“wherein a nameless universal Being does not have
final sway.”
80
Levinas sees Heideggerian ontology as an “ontology of
power which is tempted to relate to the other by murder.”
81
Instead,
infinite would identify, in the new phenomenological reduction, he who
oversteps the ontological difference” (ibid.). Thus, for Marion, this insistence
in Levinasian ethics that “the self is defined by its responsibility to the neighbor
who is always prior to the self” (ibid., 243), increases the danger of Self’s
elimination.
76 Levinas, God, Death and Time, 149.
77 Ibid., 167.
78 Ibid., 127.
79 Even though Levinas’s concept of the face-to-face relationship derives from
Husserl and Heidegger (his predecessors and mentors), it has nothing to do
with reciprocal and symmetrical intersubjectivity (Dimitrova, In Levinas’ Trace,
27). We may assume that Husserl’s phenomenology is an ontology, and
Heidegger’s fundamental ontology is a phenomenology, both trying to
thoroughly analyze the Greek term physical. Levinas contends that he has taken
a step forward, proposing that the main topic of his thinking is metaphysical.
As J. Llewellyn correctly infers in his article “Levinas, Derrida and Others Vis-
à-Vis,” in Bernasconi and Wood (eds.), The Provocation of Levinas, 136: “It is
metaphysical because it is ethical. And it is ethical not because he aims to
present a code or a metaphysics of ethics.” Llewellyn also adds that “ethical is
older than justice… [and] prior to all structures of being-with” (ibid., 137).
80 Kearney (ed.), Continental Philosophy in the 20th Century, loc. 4737.
81 Ibid., loc. 4759.
Stavros Panayiotou
Levinas proposes a different dialectic, focused on defending the
ethical community of the other. Levinas insists on the phrase ‘thou
shalt not commit no murder’:
To kill is not to dominate but to annihilate; it is to renounce
comprehension absolutely. Murder exercises a power over what
escapes power. It is still a power, for the face expresses itself in
the sensible, but already impotency, because the face rends the
sensible. The alterity that is expressed in the face provides the
unique ‘matter’ possible for total negation. I can wish to kill only
an existent absolutely independent, which exceeds my powers
infinitely, and therefore does not oppose them but paralyzes the
very power of power. The Other is the sole being I can wish to kill.
(Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 198)
However, killing in Levinas’s work is not real or pragmatist but
ethical. He is not interested in criminology or facts related to the
penal system. Levinas focuses on the ethical crime of the Other:
If the resistance to murder were not ethical but real, we would
have a perception of it, with all that reverts to the subjective in
perception. We would remain within the idealism of a
consciousness of struggle, and not in relationship with the Other,
a relationship that can turn into struggle, but already overflows
the consciousness of struggle. The epiphany of the face is ethical.
The struggle this face can threaten presupposes the
transcendence of expression.
(E. Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 199)
Ethically speaking, Levinas claims that we need to escape onto-
theology by reconsidering meaning. However, the question that
demands further consideration is this: How can we approach meaning
without infringing on it in order to speak of God outside of onto-
theology? In analytic philosophy, a number of thinkers give priority
to immanence where meaning seems to be doxic, expressing a logical
exposition. In the Western tradition, logical thinking is fundamental,
characterized by the verb ‘to be.’ Everything which is logical, thetic
and analytical posits itself as reflecting to immanence and is in itself
presence, therefore revealing onto-theology. This tradition derives
from the Greeks, who focused on profound and fundamental
experience, bringing God into onto-theology through a logical being
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
qua being. The meaning of philosophical thought is drawn from
cosmos. In Heidegger, the Same, which is the rational and the
meaningful, is what really matters.
82
Levinas, on the other hand, tries to manifest whether Ethics is a
necessary and sufficient condition to justify God outside onto-
theology. The answer is yes, if and only if we find a means to speak
about meaning “without reference to the world, to being, to
knowledge, to the Same.”
83
Ethics can provide this means, signifying
a transcendence that would not be interpreted with analytical, thetic
and doxic arguments in presence. Levinas considers the possibility, “to
transcend oneself toward the other, to go from the Same to the Other
without the Other being absorbed and adopted by the Same. If the
same can contain the Other then the Same has triumphed over the
Other.”
84
However, Levinas contends that if transcendence is focused
on appropriation (as Husserl claimed), it remains phenomenological
immanence. The in-itself indicates the triumphant truth of the Same
over the Other, suppressing all ethical transcendence.
85
For Levinas,
82 Levinas, God, Death and Time, 135.
83 Ibid., 137.
84 Ibid., 141.
85 It is worth noting that for Levinas there are two different views of subjective
truth: (a) the triumphant truth and (b) the persecuted truth. Both terms are
invented and discussed by Kierkegaard, as Levinas notes in his work Proper
Names, ch. 8: “Kierkegaard: Existence and Ethics,” 1996b, pp. 66-74. Levinas
explains that the triumphant truth, as Kierkegaard calls it, derives from
idealism, and especially from the Hegelian dialectic of egocentric orientation
of the subject. Truth triumphs, as Hegel explains, by “letting the human subject
be absorbed by the Being that this subject uncovered. Idealism claimed that the
unfolding of Being by thought allowed the subject to rise above itself and hand
over its last secrets to Reason” (ibid. 66). This line of thought, in brief,
culminates in the triumph of absolute Being and Reason, which both empower
the self to be nominated as the core center of meaning and all reality. The self
is universal and alone controls and commands everything through totalization
and apprehension of Being: “Being was the correlate of thought” (ibid., 67). On
the other hand, Levinas credits Kierkegaard’s contribution in presenting a
counter-argument against the above idealistic proposition. He proposes that
subjectivity is irreducible to objective being (ibid., 68). Hence, truth must not
be considered as a triumphant perfect realization of Being which totalizes
experience, but as a “belief linked to a truth that suffers” (ibid., 69): as truth
persecuted. By persecution, Kierkegaard means that “it is through suffering
truth that one can describe the very manifestation of the divine: simultaneity
of All and Nothingness, Relation to a Person both present and absent -- to a
humiliated God who suffers, dies and leaves those whom he saves in despair. A
certainty that coexists with an absolute uncertainty-to the point that one may
Stavros Panayiotou
the phenomenon of transcendence (of the infinite) is based on “the
responsibility of the neighbor,” an aimless meaning without vision.
86
Levinasian ethics gives priority not to doxic ontological criteria but to
paradoxical transcendence toward the Other and not toward the Self.
Levinas strongly favored the subversion of phenomenological
immanence, turning to the phenomenon of enjoyment which does
not credit “self-constituting or the primacy of the same over the
other” but rather “the privilege of the other over the self.”
87
For
Levinas, “paradox inscribes the glory of the infinite in the
relationship called intersubjective.”
88
Hence, Levinas states that we
can speak of God escaping onto-theology if and only if the Other as a
nonthematizable, invisible interlocutor reveals prior freedom and
essence in our intersubjective self. Ethics cannot be interpreted as
knowledge of being and comprehension; instead, it is the relationship
between me and the other, the neighbor. However, in contrast to the
Christian Triadic God,
89
the neighbor comes to me first without any
wonder whether that Revelation itself is not contrary to the essence of that
crucified truth, whether God's suffering and the lack of recognition of the truth
would not reach their highest degree in a total incognito” (ibid., 69). However,
Levinas notes a problematic point in Kierkegaard’s discussion of the distinction
between triumphant and persecuted truth. He contends that Kierkegaard’s
contribution to existential philosophy and his correct critique on Hegel and
Idealism leaves out something crucial: responsibility. Levinas underlines that
“[True] Subjectivity is in that responsibility and only irreducible subjectivity
can assume a responsibility. That is what constitutes the ethical. To be myself
means, then, to be unable to escape responsibility” (ibid., 73), an idea that is
marginal in Kierkegaard’s thought. Thus, persecuted truth for Levinas starts
from Kierkegaard but ends with responsibility for the Other who chases me,
eternally driving me into infinity. And the Other “is the poor, the destitute, and
nothing about that Stranger can be indifferent to it […and] I am responsible for
the very one who commands me.” (ibid., 74).
86 Levinas, God, Death and Time, 142.
87 Kearney (ed.), Continental Philosophy in the 20th Century, loc. 4815, 4819.
88 Levinas, God, Death and Time, 162.
89 Levinas would strongly reject views such as: “the clearest personal expression
of religion and the view of God as Trinity (Τριάς) exists in the relations that
make us persons [...] Τhe search for meaning in Christian spirituality is enacted
primarily by entering into relationship with Christ and the Blessed Trinity [...]
God the Father corresponds to our carbon relations because the Father is the
creator of the carbon universe” (K.A. Bryson, “The Ways of Spirituality,Sophia
Philosophical Review X.2 (2017): 11). Such a direct communication with God
reduces God to our minds and therefore we then speak of onto-theology. For
Levinas, the ‘face of God’ is irreducible to finite human beings. The structure of
spirituality depends neither on rational theology (as in several Christian
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
specific criteria or preconditions. Levinasian ethics is beyond freedom
and essence; rather, it is about responsibility and reciprocal
authenticity. Ethical relationship is a responsibility for the other. “It
is not a disclosure of something given but the exposure of the me to
another, prior to any decision.”
90
In parallel Levinas states that ethical
relationship, in contrast to onto-theology, is “a responsibility that
obsesses, one that is an obsession, for the other besieges me, to the
point where he puts in question my for-me, my in-itself, to the point
where he makes me a hostage.”
91
Thus we can infer that autonomy, in
Levinas’s view, can be marginalized. What matters in this sense is
heteronomy.
92
The latter is ultimate the former is not, as
doctrines such as Catholics and Protestants) nor on ascetic contemplation (i.e.,
Orthodoxy). For Levinas, when the Holy is reduced to the Sacred, we are left
with idolatry and rational theology which are both unacceptable. See Levinas,
Part II: “Transcendence, Idolatry and Secularization,” in his work God, Death and
Time, 163-66.
90 Levinas, God, Death and Time, 187.
91 Ibid., 138. The term ‘hostage’ is mistakenly construed by some thinkers as they
confuse it with the modern term imprisoner or being taken violently by
someone, i.e. slavery or servitude. By saying that ‘I am eternally hostage toward
the Other’, Levinas means that responsibility precedes freedom and autonomy:
“a responsibility that obsesses, one that is an obsession, for the other besieges
me, to the point he makes me a hostage” (ibid.). As Saracino correctly
underlines, “as hostage for-the-Other, the subject is called to care for the Other
in non-totalizing ways, that is, by the way of gestures of justice, generosity and
sacrifice” (M. Saracino, On Being Human: A Conversation with Lonergan and Levinas
[Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 2003], 96).
92 Concerning the difference between autonomy and heteronomy, Levinas gives
priority to heteronomy: he states that “subjectivity, as responsible, is a
subjectivity which is commanded at the outset; heteronomy is somehow
stronger than autonomy here, except that this heteronomy is not slavery, is
not bondage […] The responsibility for the other comes from the hither side of
my freedom” (Levinas,
Of God Who Comes to Mind, 111, 114). See further
comments in A. Strhan, Levinas, Subjectivity, Education, 2012, 73-94. J. Raz, in
addition, defines autonomy by claiming that “the autonomous person is a (part)
author of his own life. The ideal of personal autonomy is the vision of people
controlling, to some degree, their own destiny, fashioning it through successive
decisions throughout their lives” (J. Raz, The Morality of Freedom [Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1986], 369). For Levinas, this statement would be correct to
define autonomy, but lacks ethical content. If the autonomous person is the
author of his life, controlling his own destiny, egology and ontology appear to
a high degree. If all my thought is focused on how to build and maintain my
personal pursuit of happiness above all, this is for Levinas Ontology. Autonomy
produces an equal-to-thought status (Levinas,
Of God Who Comes to Mind, 180)
whereas the Other is inevitably marginalized for the sake of self-interest and
Stavros Panayiotou
heteronomous ethics is assumed in infinite responsibility. In parallel,
eros and agape (love)
93
are “breaking out of monadism and the
egocentric predicament, where the self agapeically goes towards the
other as other.”
94
The self is for the other and not the other for the
self. In this sense, difference or différance
95
of the other as hostage
96
gives priority to religion and ethics to speak of God outside onto-
theology, since the I ( ν) depends on the Other as an interlocutor,
and not the Other on the I. Thus the I, according to Levinas, must be
transformed into the accusative case: “me.” “Me” needs someone else
in order to exist; it cannot be alone. “Me” (in accusative case)
97
needs
Sameness. Levinas develops his thought concerning autonomy and its
integration into reason in his work Entre Nous, ch. 15: “Uniqueness,” 190-91.
93 When Levinas was asked about the difference between Eros/love and Agape, he
confessed: “I do not think that Agape comes from Eros […] Eros is definitely not
Agape, that Agape is neither a derivative nor the extinction of love-Eros. Before
Eros there was the Face; Eros itself is possible only between Faces. The problem
of Eros is philosophical and concerns otherness […] I have a grave view of Agape
in terms of responsibility for the other” (Levinas Of God Who Comes to Mind, 113).
Eros has a dramatic nostalgia which remains to presence. Levinas contends that
love as agape has more ethical and metaphysical repercussions. For Levinas,
“love [as agape] desires not a nostalgic return to stasis but reaches out instead
towards the other and ultimately towards a future: the impossibility or failure
of fusion is the very positivity of love” (S. Sandford, The Metaphysics of Love:
Gender and Transcendence in Levinas [London: The Athlone Press, 2000], 97).
94 Kearney (ed.), Continental Philosophy in the 20th Century, loc. 4924, 4932.
Concerning the phenomenology of Eros, see P. Moyaert, “The Phenomenology
of Eros: A Reading of Totality and Infinity,” in Bloechl (ed.) The Face of the Other
and the Trace of God, 30-42.
95 The term différance is developed by J. Derrida and it is adopted also by Levinas
in order to explain the importance of transcendence over immanence. In
deconstruction and post-modern philosophy, according to Derrida, subject
must be decentered and must be replaced by intersubjective conditions beyond
knowledge and logic. Differ, according to Derrida, means to differ from itself.
For Derrida, différance is not an analytical concept or even a word. It is not what
we represent to ourselves as beings. “It is the nonfull, nonsimple origin: it is
the structured and differing origin of differences” (Kearney and Rainwater
[eds.], Continental Philosophy Reader, 449). “It is a trace of something that can
never present itself; It is a trace that lies beyond what profoundly ties
fundamental ontology to phenomenology” (ibid., 459). Levinas insists that in
this way we can speak of God outside onto-theology.
96 As Levinas states, “for all eternity, the I were the first one called to this
responsibility; non-transferable and thus unique, thus I, the chosen hostage,
the chosen one. An ethics of the meetingsociality. For all eternity, one man is
answerable for another” (Levinas, Entre Nous, 227).
97 Levinas writes, “Everything is from the start in the accusative. Such is the
exceptional condition or unconditionality of the self, the signification of the
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
the Other as an equal interlocutor
98
in order to be meaningful.
According to Levinas, “pre-reflective, non-intentional consciousness
would never be able to return to a moral realization of this passivity.
The non-intentional is from the start passivity and the accusative [is]
its first case (me and not I).”
99
One must speak in me and not in I. As
Blaise Pascal observes, the I is “hateful”;
100
“one has to respond to
one’s right to be.”
101
We can assume that Levinas is in favor of a
transcendence, in the sense of “the awaiting without something
awaited.”
102
Such a transcendence “without aiming and without
vision” tends to speak of God or to see God outside onto-theology.
103
In this sub-chapter, I do not intend to delve into the ontological
sphere. Rather, I seek to explain Levinas’s ethics through criticism of
fundamental ontology and onto-theology. In ethics, as Levinas
observes, the concept of the ontological “I” urgently needs to be
changed to the accusative case “me”; and as Levinas states, “no one
could replace me.”
104
An ethical I-Thou relationship, as well as the
relationship between an individual and God, needs not to be
systematized. Instead, each one relates to the other through
responsibility. However, a relation between two people is direct,
while the relation between a human and God is indirect. According to
Levinas, “the absolutely other is the Other (Autrui). He and I do not
form a number. The collectivity in which I say you or we is not a plural
of the I. I, you - these are not individuals of a common concept […]
Alterity is possible only starting from me [and not from “I” or ego].”
105
pronoun self for which our Latin grammars themselves know no nominative
form.” (Levinas, Otherwise Than Being, 112).
98 Levinas, Entre Nous, 4-9. By the term “ethical interlocutor,” I do not mean a
procedure where the other will be absorbed by sameness. Dialogue and equal
response in Levinasian ethics is not the same as the connection of parole and
langue to language. In Levinas’s ethics, by saying that the other must be equal
interlocutor we mean that the Same allows the Other to show her otherness in
an equal procedure without coercion, [Hegelian] power or [Husserlian]
noematic-horizontal intentionality.
99 Kearney and Rainwater (eds.), The Continental Philosophy Reader, 129.
100 B. Pascal, Pensées (New York: E.P. Dutton, 1958), Part I, 1, 2, c. 1, section 4.[44],
v. 455.
101 Kearney and Rainwater (eds.), The Continental Philosophy Reader, 130.
102 Levinas, God, Death and Time, 139.
103 Ibid., 139.
104 Ibid., 152.
105 Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 39-40.
Stavros Panayiotou
The “Holiness of the Holy”: Otherness Precedes Asceticism
Levinas speaks about the Other in the context of the “ethics of
holiness.” The holy is a significant concept in Levinas’s thought.
Derrida reports a short conversation with Levinas where the latter
said: “You know, one often speaks of ethics to describe what I do, but
what really interests me in the end is not ethics, not ethics alone, but
the holy, the holiness of the holy.”
106
The idea of sanctity or holiness
has not often been discussed by scholars interested in Levinasian
ethics.
107
Yet throughout his works, Levinas insists on distinguishing
the holy from the sacred.
108
In his usage, the term “holiness” is similar
to “desacralization.” His intention was to deconstruct the meaning of
the term “sacred,” since he saw it as reduced to mystical theology,
something unacceptable in his eyes.
109
Levinas criticizes several
106 J. Derrida, Adieu: To Emmanuel Levinas, trans. P-A., Brault and M. Naas (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 1999), 4.
107 Two articles of immense importance on Levinas’s interest in sanctity can be
found in J. Hansel, “Utopia and Reality: The Concept of Sanctity in Kant and
Levinas,” Philosophy Today 43.2 (1999): 16875 and J. Caruana, “Levinas’s Critique
of the Sacred,International Philosophical Quarterly 42.4 (2002) 51934. For
Levinas, sanctity has an allegoric meaning and has nothing to do with idolatry.
Levinas integrates the concept of sanctity with death. As he himself mentions,
sanctity appears metaphysically and ethically when “the death of the other can
have priority over my own death,” precisely when “the death of the other
matters more than my own.” Thus we can call this procedure sanctity, which
derives from biblical ethical law (https://www.youtube.com/
watch?v=qbGaXEqxSvU: 46:40-47:04).
108 Levinas rejects the notion of religion as sacred for the same reason that he
abhors mysticism. Both terms support immanence and ignore the direct
separation of God and humans.
109 For Levinas, God is neither an idea nor a being, not because there is a kind of
mystical knowledge that we (as humans) do not have the rational ability to
surpass, but mainly because there is a “brick wall” between me as a finite
human and God as infinite transcendence. Beyond this wall there is something
I cannot think of, I cannot see, because of mypersonal stupidity(Large, “The
Name of God: Kripke, Levinas and Rozenweig on Proper Names,” 322). However,
when Large says “stupidity,” he does not mean that humans are stupid or
disabled, but he means that humans’ rational and finitude logos cannot explain
what it is to be God because they are of different essences. According to Large,
there are three possible ways to think of God: as an idea, as a being or as a word.
He then claims that the first two alternatives for Levinas are impossible since
God is transcendence and cannot be reduced to immanence. However,
according to Large, Levinas accepts the fact that God can be named as a word.
It would seem quite absurd to allege that God is a word, but what Large means
by the phrase “God is a word” is that God is a name and not a description. In
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
sociologists who were unable to distinguish between the notions le
sacré and le saint.
110
Additionally, he refers to Plato
111
in order to show
that holiness is of immense importance for ethics, not as a theological
term but as an ethical one.
112
Levinas defends the thesis that the
sacred, as well as mysticism, strengthen immanence and the ego’s
conditions, thus slipping away from transcendence and infinity.
The rigorous affirmation of human independence, of its
intelligent presence to an intelligible reality, the destruction of
the numinous concept of the Sacred, entail the risk of atheism.
That risk must be run. Only through it can man be raised to the
spiritual notion of the Transcendent. It is a great glory for the
Creator to have set up a being who affirms Him after having
contested and denied Him in the glamorous areas of myth and
enthusiasm; it is a great glory for God to have created a being
Judaism, the word God cannot be described by presenting ritual attributes to
God. Rather, the safest path to approach God is the prohibition of decorating
His essence with cosmic attributes. Thus, we can infer that the allegoric
reference to God as a word can only be construed as responsibility for the
Other. Levinas queries: “Does not the transcendence of the name of God in
comparison to all thematization become effacement and is not this effacement
the very commandment that obligates me to the other man?” (Levinas Levinas,
“The Name of God According to a Few Talmudic Texts,124). To express God’s
name, what matters is the Other; when I address the Other even someone
lowly I address God. “As the stranger passes, so too does God” (Large, The
Name of God,” 331). Therefore, I would strongly agree with Large’s implication
that “the word ‘God’ names for Levinas is the ethical responsibility for the
Other. It does not name a being with certain properties or attributes, nor an
idea necessary for human freedom” (ibid. 332). The terms stranger, meek,
humble and hostage are used a number of times by Levinas. On the crucial role
of and encounter with the stranger, see particularly R. Bernet, “The Encounter
with the Stranger: Two Interpretations of the Vulnerability of the Skin,” in
Bloechl (ed.), The Face of the Other and the Trace of God, 43-61; R. Bernasconi, “The
Alterity of the Stranger and the Experience of the Alien,” in Bloechl (ed.) The
Face of the Other and the Trace of God, 62-62-89.
110 E. Levinas,
“Secularism and the Thought of Israel,” trans. N. Poller.
in Unforeseen History (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2004) 113; idem,
Otherwise Than Being, 11-14.
111 It is worth noting that Levinas was a great admirer of Plato’s philosophy,
expressing his gratitude for how he had developed the history of philosophy,
theology and ethics by saying that “Philosophy is Platonic.” (Levinas Alterity
and Transcendence, ix).
112 See comments on Plato in Levinas, Collected Philosophical Papers, 23.
Stavros Panayiotou
capable of seeking Him or hearing Him from afar, having
experienced separation and atheism.
(Levinas, Difficult Freedom, 15-16)
Levinas shares with Plato and Kant a distrust of any religious
experience for the sake of the uniting of transcendence. For Levinas,
reconciling the sacred with the holy is a ridiculous endeavor, as the
former relates to ritual concepts and the latter to transcendence.
According to the analytic thinker Durkheim, the sacred is a
“catchword meant to capture the totality of religious experience.”
113
In parallel, another analytic thinker, Bataille, contends that
“everything leads us to the conclusion that in essence the sacramental
quality of primitive sacrifices is analogous to the comparable element
in contemporary religions.”
114
Levinas reproves both of these scholars
by promoting a more ethical intuition. He explains, as a Jewish
thinker,
115
that Judaism “consists in understanding this holiness of
God in a [different] sense [than analytic thinkers] that stands in sharp
contrast to the numinous meaning of this term, as it appears in the
primitive religions wherein the moderns have often wished to see the
source of all religion.
116
In ordinary speech, according to Levinas and
Buber,
117
the meaning of sacred is imbued with power and cosmic
113 J. Caruana, “‘Not Ethics, Not Ethics Alone, but the Holy’: Levinas on Ethics and
Holiness,” The Journal of Religious Ethics 34.4 (2006): 563.
114 G. Bataille, Eroticism, trans. M. Dalwood, (London and New York: Marion Boyars,
1962), 22.
115 It is worth noting that Levinas never proclaimed himself as a Jewish theologian,
but rather a thinker who comes from a Judaic and Talmudic angle, where his
texts run parallel with his philosophical (not religious) works. Scholars such as
S. Rosenberg, S. Wygoda, C. Chalier and D. Banon have revealed the importance
of Levinas’s thought for the understanding of Judaism today. Concerning the
contribution of the above thinkers as regards Levinas’s Jewish thought
throughout his works, see E. Meir, “Hellenic and Jewish in Levinas’ Writings,”
Veritas 51.2 (2006): 79-88.
116 E. Levinas, Difficult Freedom: Essays on Judaism, trans. S. Hand (Baltimore: Athlone
Press and John Hopkins University Press, 1990), 14.
117 A comprehensive article on Buber and Levinas is R. Bernasconi’s “’Failure of
Communication’ as a Surplus: Dialogue and Lack of Dialogue between Buber and
Levinas,” in Bernasconi and Wood (eds.), The Provocation of Levinas, 100-135. It is
obvious that Levinas disagrees with Buber’s enthusiastic intention to imbue
reciprocity to the I-Thou relation. Levinas intends to link heteronomy and
transcendence, claiming that the autonomous is primarily linked to ontology,
isolating the subject to itself absorbing otherness and the face of the other is
being subordinated to Hegelian totalization. See Levinas, Of God who Comes to
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
religious experience, something that God does not welcome.
118
It is
only with sanctification as holiness that religion can find genuine
expression. Rational individuation must be transformed into moral
separateness through the holiness which can only be found in ethics.
Levinas hence insists on the transformation of the sacred through an
ethical perspective into holiness or sanctification:
The numinous or the sacred envelops and transports man
beyond his powers and wishes. ...The numinous annuls the links
between persons by making beings participate, albeit
ecstatically, in a drama not brought about willingly by them, an
order in which they lose themselves.
(Levinas, Difficult Freedom, 14)
Levinas thus tries to argue that what matters is not a ritual sacred
experience, which is merely an action in the world, but rather an
ethical holiness which h exceeds ontological practices. On the one
hand, holiness for Levinas is the only way to access (genuine) religion.
On the other hand, the sacred consists of “a seething subjective mass
of forces, passions and imaginings.”
119
Once the sacred rite separates
the finite self from the divine, there is no possibility for the self to be
called from the other as she loses her identity. This dissolution affects
the relationship between the ‘me’ and the other and thus the
ego/being returns into itself.
What we need, in Levinas’s eyes, is a massive return to
desacralization through ethics. For Levinas, the ethical character of
the holy is the nonrational surplus that emerges not from ontological
practices but from anarchy. Holiness and ethics stem from the same
anarchic source.
120
As Levinas points out, “To say of God that he is the
God of the poor, the God of justice, involves a claim not on his
Mind, 150: “[…] in Buber, the I-Thou relationship is frequently also described as
the pure face-to-face of the encounter, as a harmonious co-presence as an eye
to eye […] In this extreme formalization the Relation empties itself of its
‘heteronomy’ and of its transcendence of association […] There would be an
inequality, a dissymmetry, in the Relation, contrary to the reciprocity upon
which Buber insists, no doubt in error”.
118 M. Buber, “Dialogue,” in Between Man and Man, trans. R.G. Smith (New York:
Macmillan, 1968), 15.
119 Levinas, Difficult Freedom, 102.
120 Caruana, “‘Not Ethics, Not Ethics Alone, but the Holy’: Levinas on Ethics and
Holiness,” 569.
Stavros Panayiotou
attributes but on his essence.”
121
Here Levinas means that the sacred
is connected to attributes of God while the holy relates to His essence.
In other words, it is holy that is transcendent and not the sacred. As
Levinas states, on the basis of the Torah, we can assume that the
sacred is equal to idolatry where, in contrast, holiness represents “the
absolute opposite to idolatry”.
122
For Levinas, idolatry has increased
not because of the intervention of other gods, but because of moral
indifference, as well as worship of the being itself. This is the reason
that monotheism is so strictly observed in Judaism, because God in the
Old Testament “does not give Himself over to human fantasies.
123
From the Old Testament, however, we also learn that people
become moral objects, not through their response and obedience to
God’s commandments, but by violating them. Man became a moral
being after eating the fruit from the tree of knowledge and began to
distinguish good from evil. Since then, he began imitating God and
wanted to become the master of human fate. Levinas blames both
Christianity and paganism for one and the same sin of idolatry. As
paganism created its gods according to the norms of the time and
began to pray to the forces of nature as gods, so Christianity created
an image of God to befit human representations and began to pray in
front of icons that replaced God or the Absolute Other. While in
Christianity, man is the image and likeness of God and prayers begin
with ‘my God’, the Hebrew God retains his position of exteriority
God is the Absolute Other, God is Transcendence that even could not
be named. Levinas insisted that Transcendence could not be
contained within the ideas of it, nor could it be embodied. For Levinas,
true monotheism is not compatible with my belief in myths or with
idolatry.
124
Does holiness affect us in our contact with the divine? In short,
is holiness a channel in between the human and God? The answer,
121 Levinas, “Secularism and the Thought of Israel,” 116.
122 Idem, Beyond the Verse: Talmudic Readings and Lectures, 58.
123 Idem, Difficult Freedom, 102.
124 Dimitrova, Sociality and Justice, 79.
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
according to Levinas, comes through negation
125
neither/nor.
126
Levinas states that “the infinite who orders me is neither a cause
acting straight on, nor a theme, already dominated, if only
retrospectively, by freedom.
127
He adds that “this detour is the enigma
128
of a trace we have called illeity.
129
Illeity is a term coined by Levinas
to indicate a special symbolic allegory. It contains three different
words or endings in one word: il (he), ille (she) and -ty (it, as an object).
Levinas’s use of this term aims at indicating “a way of concerning me
(and not I) without entering into conjunction with me.”
130
In my view,
the neologism illeity constitutes a counter to the Buberian I-Thou
dyadic scheme,
131
since, as Levinas says, “illeity lies outside the ‘thou’
125 Negation for Levinas plays a decisive role in understanding the subjectivity of
persons. Not as Hegel understands negation, that is, as power and totalization
through the dialectic of Master and Slave, but as “total negation, which spans
the infinity of that attempt and its impossibility is the presence of the face.
To be in relation with the other face to face is to be unable to kill” (Levinas Of
God Who Comes to Mind, 10). This inability to deny the other, the incapacity to
negate her “noumenal glory […] makes the face-to-face situation possible. The
face-to-face situation is thus an impossibility of denying, a negation of
negation” (ibid., 34-35).
126 See D. Braine, “Negative Theology,” in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(London: Taylor and Francis, viewed 15 October 2019).
127 Levinas, Otherwise Than Being, 12.
128 Levinas prefers the term enigma over than Kierkegaard’s silence, to develop his
argument regarding God’s trace in the world. For Levinas, the interconnection
between God and humans is an enigma, that is, God’s trace which can be found
only through the face of the other: “The semantics of the enigma breaks out of
the order of autonomous thought, whereby the enigmatic as such becomes
visible only as a trace which means that it cannot be expressed by a direct
representation of language (i.e., the sign or the signifier). The enigma is,
according to Levinas, always older than, it is presupposed by, the intellectual
cognition; but it cannot be reduced to a coherent system” (M.T. Mjaaland,
Autopsia: Self, Death and God after Kierkegaard and Derrida, trans. B. McNeil [Berlin-
New York: Walter de Gruyter, 2008], 127). Concerning Levinas’s view on enigma
as an ethical phenomenon, see Levinas, Collected Philosophical Papers, 1987, 61-73.
129 Levinas, Otherwise Than Being, 12.
130 Ibid., 12.
131 From my point of view, A.K. Min correctly points out that “the true Infinite is
revealed and accessible only as illeity, neither as a [Buberian] Thou of
unmediated dialogue nor as an [Husserlian horizon] object of thematization”
(Min 2006: 102). Concerning the notion of Husserl’s concept of horizon, see J.
Mensch, “Life and Horizon”, Sophia Philosophical Review XI.2 (2018), 7-18. Min
borrows two phrases from Levinas’s work God, Death and Time: that the true
Infinite is revealed only as “a way of concerning me without entering into
Stavros Panayiotou
and the thematization of objects.”
132
Levinas goes on to say that “the
illeity in the beyond-being is the fact that its coming toward me is a
departure which lets me accomplish a movement toward a
neighbor”.
133
In parallel, Levinas contends that illeity “is excluded
from being, but orders it in relation to a responsibility, in relation to
its pure passivity, a pure 'susceptibility': an obligation to answer
preceding any questioning which would recall a prior commitment,
extending beyond any question, any problem and any representation,
and where obedience precedes the order that has furtively infiltrated
the soul that obeys.”
134
Ultimately, what is the connection between holiness and illeity?
Levinas claims that “illeity overflows both cognition and the enigma
through which the Infinite leaves a trace in cognition. Its distance
from a theme, its reclusion, its holiness, is not its way to effect its
being (since its past is anachronous and anarchic, leaving a trace
which is not the trace of any presence), but is its glory, quite different
from being and knowing.”
135
The call of the other is holy and dramatic. The drama of being
can be overcome by holiness through the face of the other. Levinas
tries to present a “battle” between me, the Other, and God outside
ontotheology,
136
between an ontological drama and an eschatological
conjunction with me" (Levinas, God, Death and Time, 285) or as "the non-
phenomenality of the Other who affects me beyond representation,
unbeknownst to me and like a thief" (ibid. 201). Thus, Min clearly separates his
thesis from Husserl’s Ontology. In parallel, contrary to Buber’s I-Thou, Levinas
stresses that “there is no initial equality […] Ethical inequality: subordination
to the other, original diacony: the first person accusative and not nominative”
(H. Jodalen and J. Vetlesen [eds.], Closeness: An Ethics [Oslo: Scandinavian
University Press, 1997], 48, 52, n. 2). Another reproach that Levinas has against
the Buberian I-Thou relationship is that it seems quite symmetrical and
reciprocal; those two terms are unacceptable in Levinas’s philosophical
approach.
132 Levinas, Otherwise Than Being, 12.
133 Ibid., 13.
134 Idem, Beyond the Verse: Talmudic Readings and Lectures, 128.
135 Levinas, God, Death and Time, 183.
136 Levinas, as a Jewish thinker, derives several times from Talmudic aspects.
Levinas underlines that “monotheism would thus be asserted in its absolute
vigour without it being from the onto-theological perspective” (Levinas, Beyond
the Verse: Talmudic Readings and Lectures, 164), but the essence of God (En-Sof in
Talmudic writings, which means infinity, God) “is hidden away more than any
secret, and no name must name it” […] “not even the end of the smallest letter”
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
one, where both dramas can only be surpassed by an ethical
’intrigue’ not an ethical experience
137
where holiness (as ethical
sanctification) tries to escape from the ritual-cosmic sacred. In
parallel, in order to understand the holiness of the other, we can say
that it is not me who knocks on the door of the other human so he will
open it to me; rather, the other already finds me prior to freedom and
autonomy. The other’s presence “hits me straight on with the
straightest, shortest, and most direct movement”.
138
In parallel,
Levinas connects the prohibition of the sacred with the directness of
the face of the other with its proximity.
The comprehension of God taken as participation in his sacred
life, an allegedly direct comprehension, is impossible, because
participation is a denial of the divine and because nothing is
more direct than the face to face, which is straightforwardness
itself [....] There can be no ‘knowledge’ of God separated from the
relationship with men.
(Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 78)
The straight line between me and the Other’s uprightness forbids
me to participate in the sacred; it sobers me.
(Levinas, Outside the Subject, 94)
In conclusion, we can infer that holiness is an ethical tool for Levinas
to shape his intuition about the indirect connection between humans
and God and humans with the Other. In contrast to the materialistic
experience of the sacred, holiness awakes the self, outside of the
subject, in a process of ethical individuation. One of the most difficult
things for the self is to achieve awareness of his holiness towards God
and towards the Other. We come closer to meeting this challenge only
through the progressive paradox of Ethics.
(ibid.). For Levinas only the “act of thinking of the Absolute which never
reaches the Absolute is infinite and never-ending” (ibid.).
137 J. Caruana, “The Drama of Being: Levinas and the History of Philosophy,”
Continental Philosophical Review 40 (2007): 251-73.
138 Levinas, Alterity and Transcendence, 95.
Stavros Panayiotou
Is Asceticism a Necessary and Sufficient Condition in
Levinasian Ethics?
In this paper I argue that the term asceticism in Levinas’s thought
differs from the use of the term in the Patristic and Thomistic
traditions. While Aquinas and several orthodox Fathers of Eastern
Christianity contend that asceticism begins and derives from a Man-
God affirmation, Levinas raises severe objections to this approach. For
Levinas, kenosis
139
has its starting point not with God’s direct
mediation between subjectivity and human beings, nor the Greek
μίμησις (imitation), but with the movement towards dispossession.
This movement is revealed in the Biblical kenotic approbation from
me (in the accusative) to the Other, who appears as a trace of God
before my freedom and my subjectivity.
For Levinas, we can speak of asceticism only regarding human
affairs when a person, emptying herself for the sake of the other,
sacrifices her inner narcissism in favor of the otherness which
precedes freedom and autonomy.
140
Thus, we can infer that asceticism
is necessary and sufficient condition if and only if it is focused on the
face-to-face relation without absorbing otherness into itself.
141
As R.
Cohen correctly states, “the only alterity sufficiently other to provoke
response, to subject the subject to the subjection of response is the
absolute alterity of the other person encountered in the excessive
immediacy of the face-to-face”.
142
In brief, asceticism is useless and
empty of spiritual concreteness if it returns to the subject.
At the same time, Levinas rejects any conversation about
asceticism and self-emptiness related to infinity and
139 Baird, “Whose Kenosis?,” 423-37.
140 Levinas, in his work Entre Nous, chapter four, A Man-God?, 60, wonders: “How
can I expect another to sacrifice himself for me without requiring the sacrifice
of others? How can I admit his responsibility for me without immediately
finding myself, through my condition as hostage, responsible for his
responsibility itself. To be me is always to have one more responsibility.”
141 Ibid., 58, in which he reminds us, through a Biblical verse (Jeremiah 22:16) that
what matters, in approaching God, can be achieved only through the face of the
Other: “He judged the cause of the poor and needy... Was not this to know me?
saith the Lord.” Ben-Pazi’s view on forgiveness and reconciliation among
human beings is quite connected to individuals’ kenosis for the sake of the other.
See H. Ben-Pazi, “Levinasian Thoughts on Witnessing: Forgiveness, Guilt, and
Reconciliation,” South African Journal of Philosophy 35.3 (2016): 345-58.
142 R.A. Cohen, Ethics, Exegesis and Philosophy: Interpretation after Levinas (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2004), 139.
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
Transcendence.
143
It is impossible, philosophically speaking, to
develop or predict an “idea of a self-inflicted humiliation on the part
of the Supreme Being, of a descent of the Creator to the level of the
Creature; that is to say, an absorption of the most active activity into
the most passive passivity”.
144
Levinas also wonders whether God,
who manifests Himself in the world through his covenant, can Himself
become present in the time of the world? Levinas’s answer is no,
because time in God’s essence is immemorial, and we can seek Him
only through the face of the Other as a trace and proximity. Moreover,
Levinas rejects divine ascetic onto-theology of Western tradition
because “the Infinite cannot incarnate itself in a Desirable, cannot,
being infinite, enclose itself in an end. It solicits through a face. A Thou
is inserted between the I and the absolute He. It is not history's
present that is the enigmatic interval of a humiliated and
transcendent God, but the face of the Other.”
145
The meaning of ascetic kenosis in Levinas’s thought, as opposed
to onto-theological and Christological perspectives, can be grasped
only if we construe Levinas’s ethics from an anthropological angle. As
R.D.N. van Riessen correctly contends, “as a Jewish thinker Levinas
relates the kenosis of God and the self-emptying of the subject to each
other without reference to the figure of Christ”.
146
Similarly, A. Wells
underlines that for Levinas a “non-immanental ethical interaction
can occur without the Absolute Paradox (i.e., the God-man, Christ).
One need not be Christian to recognize the Other’s transcendence.
Every Other, on Levinas’s reading, is sufficiently enigmatic to force a
break with immanence.”
147
143 In this case, Transcendence is God, an absent God, which has no direct
involvement with human affairs. E. Meir, in his work “Hellenic and Jewish in
Levinas’s Writings,” 83, states characteristically that “direct contact with Him
is absent; the mediation of reasons and of a teaching, of the Torah, is required.
In this way, a place is created for consciousness and knowledge. The idea of a
God who does not forgive in place of the other man is parallel with the
Cartesian idea of the infinite, much appreciated by Levinas. God is not powerful,
but powerless, His kenosis is the humility of leaving His trace in the Other,
without forcing man to respond.”
144 Levinas, Entre Nous, 53.
145 Ibid., 58.
146 Van Riessen, Man as a Place of God: Levinas’ Hermeneutics of Kenosis, 174.
147 See A. Wells, “On Ethics and Christianity: Kierkegaard and Levinas,” The
Heythrop Journal 52 (2012): 71. In addition, Wells continues his discussion about
Levinas’s exteriority of the subject by saying that “Levinas has shown that one
does not need the Absolute Paradox (i.e., Christ) to establish ethical relations
Stavros Panayiotou
Conclusion
In this paper, I have argued that asceticism begins with the ethical
metaphysics of Otherness. On the one hand, Levinas agrees that
humility is a starting point for decentering the subject, but he holds
that what is crucial is to begin with the other and not with the self. In
contrast, onto-theology, which derives from ancient Greek tradition,
insists on consciousness and intentionality, that is, placing
individualism prior to relationalism. Therefore, in analytic and
continental philosophical traditions, as well as contemporary
religious tradition, asceticism gives priority to consciousness as well
as to the dominance of the subject, who reflects and apprehends its
own validity through its esotericism. Thus, historicity of the subject
as an enclosed-self unit echoes narcissism and its capability to
comprehend the essence of God within the self alone.
Following Hegelian totality and Heideggerian manifestation of
being qua being, subjectivity became cemented within an
epistemological framework, which seems quite sufficient to proclaim
itself absolute. In addition, Descartes’s cogito has been considered as
the culmination of cognitive dominance over metaphysics, aesthetics,
and ethics. On the other hand, post-Hegelian critique on the thinking
subject influenced various analytic and continental thinkers across
Europe. Postmodernity offers another view based on ethical
metaphysics and intersubjectivity as well as on faith and religion.
Emmanuel Levinas, for his part, introduced a new understanding of
ethics, arguing that it is the Other who gives meaning to the ascetic
self and not the opposite. Overcoming the notion of self-reflection of
the thinking subject, Levinas proposed an alternative notion of
subjectivity, claiming that what really matters is the moral
responsibility for the Other. For Levinas, God commands me through
the face of the Other, but it is my responsibility to understand and
answer. I suggest that Levinas initiated a new dialectic on asceticism:
an infinite intersubjective called by the Other as the trace of God.
148
with others. Every Other, according to Levinas, is enough of an enigma, enough
of a paradox, to force a break with immanence i.e., every Other has the power
to force the subject to relate to something outside itself” (ibid., 58).
148 R. Gibbs, in his monograph Correlations in Levinas and Rosenzweig (New Jersey:
Princeton University Press, 1992), chapter 4: “God speaks with Human
Language,” 92-100, analyzes the above argument, that is, that God’s presence-
in-the-world cannot be sustained or adopted in Levinasian Ethics, but can be
seen, through the unseen, only as a trace, through human intervention as “the
Emmanuel Levinas’s Criticism of Onto-Theology
Let us conclude with the words of R.D.N. van Riessen, who noted that
to grasp Levinas’s notion of ascetic kenosis, we need to recall Jewish
tradition: “the concept of kenosis [in the Jewish tradition] sees God’s
absence as an event which is painful but at the same time creates
space for human action.”
149
language of the meek, the orphan and the humble.” This concept has been
called by other scholars “Levinas’s a-theism”. They do not mean necessarily a
lack of a Supreme Being outside universal norms, but mainly, as W. Large points
out in his article “Atheism of the Word: Narrated Speech and the Origin of
Language in Cohen, Rosenzweig and Levinas,” Religions 9 (2018): 1, that “God is
no longer interpreted as a being necessary to understand the existence of a
rational universe; the monotheistic God is neither a being nor an idea, but the
living reality of speech. What menaces the reality of God is not whether God
exists, or is intelligible, but the externality of language without a subject.”
149 See Van Riessen, Man as a Place of God: Levinas’ Hermeneutics of Kenosis, 11.
Stavros Panayiotou