64
© 2019 by D. James Greiner
doi:10.1162/DAED_a_00536
The New Legal Empiricism &
Its Application to Access-to-Justice Inquiries
D. James Greiner
Abstract: The United States legal profession routinely deals with evidence in and out of courtrooms, but
the profession is not evidence-based in a scientific sense. Lawyers, judges, and court administrators make
decisions determining the lives of individuals and families by relying on gut intuition and instinct, not
on rigorous evidence. Achieving access to justice requires employing a new legal empiricism. It starts with
sharply defined research questions that are truly empirical. Disinterested investigators deploy established
techniques chosen to fit the nature of those research questions, following established rules of research ethics
and research integrity. New legal empiricists will follow the evidence where it leads, even when that is to
unpopular conclusions challenging conventional legal thinking and practice.
The U.S. legal profession routinely deals with ev-
idence in and out of courtrooms, but the profes-
sion is not evidence-based in the scientific sense.
Lawyers, judges, and court administrators, as they
work in the U.S. justice system, make decisions
that determine the lives of individuals and fami-
lies. But they overwhelmingly rely on gut intuition
and instinct, not on rigorous evidence. The choice
to eschew evidence matters. The profession is ask-
ing the wrong questions about topics fundamental
to our system of government, and “if they can get
you asking the wrong questions, they don’t have to
worry about answers.”
1
Here are two examples:
Judges decide which arrestees to incarcerate ver-
sus who to release pending disposition of criminal
cases in so-called bail hearings. They frequently fo-
cus on information available only from an interview
of the arrestee, such as how long they have lived in
the community, their employment situation, and
the presence of any family in the area. But arrest-
ee interviews raise concerns of self-incrimination,
d. james greiner is the Hon-
orable S. William Green Profes-
sor of Public Law and Faculty Di-
rector of the Access to Justice Lab
(
a2j) at Harvard Law School. He
has published in such journals as
Harvard Law Review, The Yale Law
Journal, and Quarterly Journal of
Political Science.
148 (1) Winter 2019 65
D. James
Greiner
and are often unavailable because arrest-
ees cannot be or do not choose to be in-
terviewed. Scientific evidence suggests
that if complete or nearly complete in-
formation on an arrestee’s past criminal
history (if any) is available–information
from existing administrative records–
an interview with the arrestee is unnec-
essary and provides little additional rele-
vant information.
2
In some jurisdictions, most low-income
survivors of domestic violence petition-
ing for civil protection orders will not re-
ceive full lawyer representation. Over-
subscribed legal-services providers often
decide to provide a few survivors/peti-
tioners full representation and to provide
something less (such as self-help materi-
als and/or an explanatory telephone call)
to most. But in making these triage deci-
sions, lawyers often ask themselves which
cases they can win (meaning obtain a civ-
il protection order), not in which cases
their representation is likely to make a
difference.
3
Winning a case and making
a difference in a case are two different
things. There is little evidence about how
to identify cases in which full representa-
tion makes a dif ference.
These examples illustrate that the ques-
tions the legal profession chooses to ask
about services it provides to poor and
low-income people have substantial con-
sequences about who spends time incar-
cerated and who obtains legal protec-
tion from abusers. In other words, these
choices have immediate consequences
for real people.
The new legal empiricism, which exists
in pockets in the academy but only rare-
ly outside of it, could transform the U.S.
legal profession into an evidence-based
field. As the examples above indicate, ra-
tionalizing those areas of law might re-
duce crime and incarceration and permit
more effective triage decisions by legal-
services providers. In other words, fewer
people could go to jail, and those who do
go might spend less time there, with no
increase in crime rates or threat to the ad-
ministration of justice. More survivors
of domestic violence could have judicial
protection orders. None of this would re-
quire additional resources.
As of the 1930s, U.S. medicine was not
yet a science either. Physicians relied al-
most exclusively on gut instinct and intu-
ition, informed by dubious claims from
drug companies, to decide which drugs
to provide patients. Over the next forty
years, medicine transformed itself into a
field in which physicians made decisions
about treatment based on evidence from
randomized controlled trials (
rcts).
4
The
U.S. population lives longer and health-
ier lives in part because of this transfor-
mation. The emergence of the new le-
gal empiricism, one hopes, indicates that
eighty-plus years later, law may begin to
follow medicine’s example.
What is the new legal empiricism? The
“new” here modifies “legal,” not “empir-
icism.” New legal empiricism is simply
strong empiricism, as developed and im-
plemented over the past decades in fields
outside of law, now finally applied to law.
It is “new” in the sense that law has fol-
lowed neither medicine nor other social
sciences (sociology, economics, political
science, psychology) in demanding that
strong empiricism become the standard
for investigations that researchers con-
duct and the basis for decisions that those
in the field make.
There are many kinds of empiricism,
and empirical projects can further a va-
riety of goals. Historians engage in em-
piricism, frequently based on archival
records and oral interviews with the el-
derly, and have their own standards of in-
ference. Literary scholars sometimes in-
vestigate the lives of the authors whose
work they interpret. The new legal em-
66 Dædalus, the Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences
The New Legal
Empiricism &
Its Application
to Access-to -
Justice Inquiries
piricism involves investigations into how
the current legal system works, and how
to change the world for the better, how-
ever “better” is defined.
The first step in strong empiricism is
sharply defining the questions to address.
The legal profession frequently fails here,
and when it does, nothing that follows
matters. Relevant questions emerge from
conversation among empiricists, prac-
titioners in a field, and their customers
or clients. In the “bail” release example
above, a judge or a legislator might con-
sult an empiricist for help in easing jail
overcrowding or ameliorating racial dis-
parities in incarceration. The empiricist
might examine jail rosters to discover
that a substantial portion of jail residents
are arrestees awaiting trial on the charges
leveled against them, examine whether
some racial groups are over- or under-
represented, and ask how decisions are
made about whom to incarcerate before
trial.
Those questions might lead to the fol-
lowing information: In practice, after a
law enforcement officer arrests some-
one, the arrestee is taken to a jail and held
there while a prosecutor files charges
against him. In most U.S. jurisdictions,
the arrestee is brought before a judge (or
the equivalent) who decides whether to
release the arrestee as he awaits trial on
those charges, and if so, what conditions
the arrestee will have to meet to secure re-
lease. As a matter of broad policy, judges
could release all arrestees, but doing so
carries risks that some arrestees will fail
to return for hearings or will commit new
crimes while on release, either of which
undermines the administration of the
case and the public’s confidence in the ju-
dicial system. Judges could release no ar-
restees, meaning incarcerate them all, but
that carries fiscal and human costs. Judg-
es in all U.S. jurisdictions, following dic-
tates of statutes and court decisions that
vary in the degree of discretion delegated
to judges and in the factors judges can or
must consider, release some arrestees and
not others, imposing conditions on all ar-
restees released. Bail is one well-known
condition: the arrestee must arrange for
the deposit of a certain amount of money,
set by a judge, into a court account, with
the money returned at the end of the case
if the arrestee meets the conditions of re-
lease, but subject to forfeit to the court if
the arrestee misbehaves.
My research suggests that judges mak-
ing predisposition release decisions are
attempting to minimize three rates: 1)
the rate at which arrestees fail to appear at
court hearings in their criminal cases; 2)
the rate at which arrestees commit crimes
(especially violent crimes) between ar-
rest and case disposition; and 3) the rate
at which arrestees are incarcerated. Judg-
es and legislators are also often concerned
about potentially unlawful racial dispari-
ties in the population of arrestees incar-
cerated at the bail stage and about wheth-
er criminal records or other risk factors
justify racial disparities observed.
With that in mind, the empiricist and
the judge or legislator might agree that the
broad question is how to rank groups of
arrestees according to the objective, un-
biased risk that they will commit crimes
or fail to appear if released. High-risk ar-
restees could be incarcerated, the remain-
der released. The empiricist might break
this broader question into two: What ob-
servable factors classify arrestees accord-
ing to their risk of committing crimes or
failing to appear, without introducing ra-
cial bias into the bail decision? And does
providing some kind of compilation or
summary of those factors, for example,
in the form of a score that classifies risk,
result in reductions of some or all of the
rates listed above?
To an empiricist, these last questions
are of different types. The first, about
148 (1) Winter 2019 67
D. James
Greiner
factors that classify (or predict) arrestee
risk of misbehavior, gets at the way the
world is. It is descriptive. The second,
about whether providing information on
risk to judges improves criminal justice
outcomes, is causal. The causal question
gets at whether doing something (pro-
viding risk information to judges) ver-
sus doing something else (not providing
risk information to judges) alters a set of
outcomes (the three rates above) in a de-
sirable way.
Once the empirical questions to be ex-
plored have been identified, the empiri-
cist must determine how to answer them.
There will always be several options: qual-
itative techniques, such as structured inter-
views of potentially knowledgeable peo-
ple; focus groups, in which an empiricist
assembles groups of potentially knowl-
edgeable people, provides them with
open-ended questions, and elicits infor-
mation from the resulting discussion;
structured observation of relevant events; or
reviewing relevant documents to look for pat-
terns. Still other options include: quantita-
tive techniques, such as surveys of random-
ly selected individuals or cases or judges;
predictive models, which explore whether
and how well precursor variables predict
the value of ultimate variables; and ran-
domized controlled trials, in which the em-
piricist randomly assigns cases, people,
judges, or units of some kind to one condi-
tion or another and then measures which
condition produces a more desirable set
of outcomes. A practitioner of the new le-
gal empiricism, like a practitioner of rig-
orous empiricism outside the legal con-
text, chooses the method appropriate for
the questions to be addressed.
To illustrate this second step, return
to the two smaller empirical questions
identified above: What factors accurate-
ly predict arrestees’ risk of misbehavior
if released on bail? And does providing
information to judges about those factors
result in better reduction of the rates of
failure to appear at hearings, new crimes
committed between arrest and case dis-
position, and incarceration?
The empiricist will choose qualitative or
quantitative techniques to address these
questions. Which ones? In many situa-
tions, qualitative techniques are either su-
perior to other options or an integral part
of an overall research plan. For these two
questions, however, I would look primar-
ily to quantitative techniques. One reason
is the objectivity of the information like-
ly to be obtained by interviewing partici-
pants in the bail hearings. The goal of the
empirical project is to improve the judg-
es’ decision-making in these hearings, so
there is reason to be cautious about rely-
ing exclusively on talking to people and
observing the settings that are the target
of improvement efforts.
Instead, researchers exploring this
question have compiled data potentially
available to judges making arrestee re-
lease decisions, such as information about
charges, arrestee criminal history, their
history of appearing or not at past hear-
ings, their ties to the community, their
race or ethnicity, and other factors. Re-
searchers have connected this informa-
tion to information about key outcomes,
such as judges’ release decisions, arrest-
ees’ failure to appear, and arrestees’ com-
mission of new crimes. Applying statisti-
cal techniques to these data, researchers
have created scoring systems or algo-
rithms relating observable information
about arrestees to release decisions, fail-
ures to appear, and new crimes.
5
The scor-
ing systems or algorithms are known as
“risk assessment” instruments or scores.
They aim to use variables that are observ-
able at release hearings and are racially
unbiased, along with a set of weights de-
rived from the data analysis exercise just
described, to classify arrestees according
68 Dædalus, the Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences
The New Legal
Empiricism &
Its Application
to Access-to -
Justice Inquiries
to the risk that they will fail to appear or
commit new crimes if released. This is
the new legal empiricism at work.
The new legal empiricism is about more
than selecting and implementing the right
research techniques to obtain and ana-
lyze the right data; it is also about creat-
ing research norms that protect the credi-
bility of the research and researcher.
New legal empiricism practitioners
must follow general norms of social sci-
ence research that have emerged to safe-
guard research integrity and the appear-
ance of research integrity. For example,
empiricists should not engage in investi-
gations in which they have a financial or
other interest that might affect their im-
partiality. Independent researchers ordi-
narily produce more credible results. Re-
searchers must also follow the evidence.
If the strong empirical techniques sug-
gest or lead to truths that are unpopular
among certain constituencies, or even
normatively creepy, the empiricist must
report those results.
New legal empiricism practitioners
should stay cognizant of the limits of re-
search techniques, and remember to in-
clude a discussion of those limits in the
publications they produce. Where possi-
ble, empiricists specify their methods and
research goals before they start doing any
research, for example, by “registering” a
proposed study on one of several websites
that exist for this purpose. Where possi-
ble, consistent with confidentiality- and
use-agreement limits frequently ground-
ed in concerns of ethics and privacy, em-
piricists make their data and statistical
code publicly available to allow replica-
tion of results.
New legal empiricism practitioners
should also separate, to the extent possi-
ble, the facts they investigate and gener-
ate from value judgments required in any
policy decision. Returning to the example
of risk assessment instruments, recall
that the aim was to minimize simultane-
ously the rates at which arrestees were in-
carcerated, failed to appear at court hear-
ings, and committed new (and especially
violent) crimes. Minimizing these rates
might involve tradeoffs: more incarcer-
ation might mean few failures to appear
and less crime. How to weigh these rates
against one another in setting policy in
this area is a value judgment, not an em-
pirical question. Though 100 percent
separation between empiricism and val-
ues is neither possible nor desirable, a
fair amount of distance between them is
achievable and essential to the empiri-
cist’s credibility.
Returning to the running example of
risk assessment instruments for bail hear-
ings, assume that the initial step of con-
structing a risk assessment instrument is
complete, so that an empiricist has iden-
tified a set of variables observable after
arrest and not too closely associated with
race that, weighted in a specified way, ap-
pears to classify arrestees according to
risk of misbehavior. Assume that the re-
searcher followed best practices with re-
spect to research integrity.
The next question is whether sharing
the risk assessment scores with judges
will change their behavior, by facilitat-
ing release decisions that minimize ra-
cial imbalances along with rates of in-
carceration, failure to appear, and/or
new criminal activity. This question is
one of program effectiveness, suggest-
ing that the backbone of research should
be one or more
rcts, because answer-
ing the research question requires being
able to compare judicial decisions (and
results of those decisions) when the risk
assessment instrument is available, and
when it is not, to see which produces
better outcomes. Only
rcts, with their
random allocation of judicial decisions
to a risk-assessment condition versus a
148 (1) Winter 2019 69
D. James
Greiner
no-risk-assessment condition, can assure
(up to statistical uncertainty) that differ-
ences observed in the outcomes are due
to the difference in conditions and not
some alternative factor.
In this example, without an
rct, a
judge might choose to use a risk assess-
ment only in cases the judge considers
close or difficult. If so, and if defendants
misbehave at higher rates in the cases
the judge considers close or difficult, a
comparison of misbehavior rates in cas-
es with risk assessment scores to misbe-
havior rates in cases without such scores
will show more misbehavior when risk
assessment scores are considered, mak-
ing it look like the risk assessment leads
to worse outcomes. An
rct would pre-
vent this kind of misrepresentation.
To answer a research question such as
this,
rcts, though necessary, are not al-
ways sufficient.
rcts will disclose wheth-
er the availability of the risk assessment
improves criminal justice outcomes but
not why it does or does not. To find out
why, a practitioner of the new legal em-
piricism should attempt to supplement
the
rcts with other quantitative tech-
niques, such as comparisons of rates of
release, failures to appear, new criminal
activity, and racial statistics before and
after the risk assessment was adopted. A
new legal empiricism practitioner should
also deploy court observations, inter-
views, and other qualitative techniques.
These techniques will generate informa-
tion about how risk assessment scores
work with judges’ decision-making, and
thus why scores do or do not help. That
information, in turn, will allow a re-
searcher to theorize about when scores
might work in other court systems.
Now imagine that several researchers
were at work on this question and they all
found the same thing: When they com-
pared release patterns, failures to appear,
new criminal activity, and racial balances
before and after the implementation of
the risk assessment program, they dis-
covered improvements in some or all of
these measures roughly coinciding with
the implementation of a risk assessment
score program. At the same time, howev-
er,
rcts showed no effect of the use of the
scores on outcomes. Interviews with judg-
es, prosecutors, defense attorneys, local
government officials, and court admin-
istrators showed that communities ordi-
narily implement risk assessment scores
as part of an overall package of criminal
justice reforms. Such reform packages in-
clude reduction of time spent in jail before
bail hearings, faster processing of infor-
mation from law enforcement to prosecu-
tors, and/or creation of programs provid-
ing differing levels of monitoring (ankle
bracelets, drug testing, automated call-
in services) that facilitate predisposition
release. In the face of 1) a favorable be-
fore-after comparison, but 2) nothing sta-
tistically significant on the
rct compari-
son that evaluated the risk assessment in-
strument exclusively, a practitioner of the
new legal empiricism might infer that the
elements of the reform packages adopted
contemporaneously with the risk assess-
ment are probably responsible for the fa-
vorable changes, not the risk assessment
itself.
The new legal empiricism means begin-
ning with a specific set of questions. The
questions to be investigated are not value
judgments masquerading as factual inqui-
ries; they are empirical. The investigation
proceeds with an impartial investigator’s
deployment of established techniques
chosen to fit the nature of the research
questions. The investigator implements
these techniques in a manner that pro-
tects the integrity of the investigation
and her own neutrality. Helpful practic-
es include prespecification, transparen-
cy, making data and coding available for
70 Dædalus, the Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences
The New Legal
Empiricism &
Its Application
to Access-to -
Justice Inquiries
replication, and defining variables clearly.
The investigator follows the evidence
where it leads, including to unpopular
conclusions, and she is careful to explain
the limits of the techniques she deploys.
All of this is new only to law.
The new legal empiricism has a great
deal to offer to the field of access to jus-
tice. The field misses out when research-
ers and their partners in the U.S. legal
profession choose not to render the re-
sults of their research credible.
Consider a question at the heart of ac-
cess to justice: how much difference, if
any, do different levels of legal assistance
make? This broad question can be ad-
dressed by identifying a particular level
of service–for example, offering self-help
materials to individuals faced with a cer-
tain kind of dispute–and identifying an
alternative level of service–for example,
offering attorney-client relationships to
individuals faced with that same kind of
dispute. Having identified differing ser-
vice levels, a researcher attempts to ascer-
tain how much each level costs as well as
the outcome variables the services are de-
signed to affect. Examples of typical out-
come variables include obtaining a favor-
able adjudicatory result, addressing the
underlying socioeconomic issue that led
to the adjudication, assuring that each lit-
igant feels that she is treated with digni-
ty and respect during the adjudication,
and reminding government officials (the
judge, the court staff) that human be-
ings are involved in each of the cases they
adjudicate.
In the past, many researchers would
have proceeded by identifying a set of
cases in which a litigant experienced one
service level (say, self-help materials)
and a set of cases in which a litigant ex-
perienced a different service level (say,
full attorney representation), comparing
the outcomes of litigants in each set, and
then attributing any observed disparities
in those outcomes to the difference in ser-
vice levels. Sometimes, such researchers
could measure observable background
variables, such as race or gender or some
measure of case complexity, and attempt
to use statistical models to “control for”
those background variables.
By contrast, a researcher working in
the new legal empiricism proceeds by de-
ploying an
rct, supplemented (ideally)
by qualitative techniques, to understand
how the adjudicatory system at issue
functions. Only an
rct can assure, up to
statistical uncertainty, that any differenc-
es observed on the outcome variables ex-
perienced by litigants with one service
level (self-help materials) versus those
experienced in another service level (full
representation) are due really to the dif-
ference in service level offered as op-
posed to, say, differences in the individu-
als’ unobservable characteristics, such as
motivation level, articulateness, or case
characteristics.
This difference in methodology goes
to the heart of what the new legal empir-
icism is and what it can offer. Practicing
lawyers say that litigants who self-select
into receiving self-help materials and lit-
igants who obtain full representation do
not have the same distribution of motiva-
tion, or articulateness, or case character-
istics. Specifically, people who success-
fully search for a legal-services provider,
find their way through its intake system,
and persuade it to provide full represen-
tation–all sufficiently early in a matter
for the attorney to provide real services–
are likely more motivated, more artic-
ulate, and have cases that have different
characteristics than those who do not. A
new legal empiricism researcher’s use of
an
rct-backboned study provides cred-
ible measurements of how much differ-
ence the disparate service levels make,
unconfounded by the effects of the dispa-
rate background variables. The new legal
148 (1) Winter 2019 71
D. James
Greiner
empiricism offers credible evidence of
the effectiveness, and cost effectiveness,
of disparate legal-service levels. Other re-
search offers little or nothing credible.
The difference in choice of method is
real. A few years ago, statistician Cassan-
dra Wolos Pattanayak and I compiled over
one hundred studies comparing the effec-
tiveness, and cost effectiveness, of legal-
services providers’ disparate levels of ser-
vice.
6
This quantity of studies addressing
the same research question demonstrates
both the question’s importance and the
vastness of the effort dedicated to answer-
ing it. But of the more than one hundred
studies, only about seven (depending on
how one counts) deployed
rct-backbone
methodology. These seven studies reach
seemingly contradictory conclusions, with
some suggesting the politically unpopu-
lar conclusion that for some legal settings,
and some sets of clients, higher (and more
expensive) levels of legal services make
little difference vis-à-vis lower, less ex-
pensive levels. The other studies are, as
detailed above, not credible. The poten-
tial of, and need for, the new legal empiri-
cism is evident.
Nonetheless, legal-services providers
continue to produce (and, apparently,
rely on) studies that do not deserve cre-
dence. Many of these are implemented by
or commissioned by the programs them-
selves. They almost invariably reach lau-
datory conclusions. By way of example,
a recent study of telephone advice pro-
grams in one state concluded that the
evaluated programs “are achieving the
primary goal of telephone-based legal as-
sistance, which is to make legal assistance
accessible to every eligible person . . .
without sacrificing service quality and ef-
fectiveness in the process.” The research-
ers arrived at this conclusion by speaking
to former clients they could reach and re-
quiring the evaluated programs to con-
duct a “self-assessment.”
7
The evaluators
spoke only to individuals who received
telephone services (and who they could
reach), so there was no comparison
group of individuals who did not receive
telephone services. There could be no
comparison necessary to conduct any kind
of evaluation, much less the randomized
evaluation needed for credibility. Here
is the essence of self-evaluation: I am the
greatest law professor on Earth. Just ask me.
This is not the new legal empiricism.
To take another example from access to
justice, consider the following narrative:
Low-income individuals frequently en-
counter civil legal problems. Most would
like to obtain attorneys to help them re-
solve those problems. The primary rea-
son they do not consult or retain attor-
neys is that they cannot afford lawyers’
fees. To further access to justice, then,
governments, philanthropists, and others
should pump money into existing legal-
services programs to fill the “justice gap.”
The narrative above has two basic
points: low-income individuals frequent-
ly encounter civil legal problems, and
most would like to obtain attorneys to
help resolve those problems but do not
do so because the cost is too high. Is the
first point true? Is the second?
For many in the U.S. legal profession,
the answers to these two questions are
too obvious to require research. As sug-
gested by the phrase “justice gap,” it sim-
ply must be the case that low-income in-
dividuals and families desire but cannot
get legal services, specifically traditional
attorney-client relationships. But a hypo-
thetical new legal empiricism researcher
would not accept the idea that truths this
important are too obvious to investigate.
An editor of this volume, Rebecca San-
defur, did not accept that idea. She sought
to find out whether low-income individ-
uals encountered legal problems and, if
so, whether they wanted attorney assis-
tance, by asking low-income individuals.
72 Dædalus, the Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences
The New Legal
Empiricism &
Its Application
to Access-to -
Justice Inquiries
Deploying a well-executed set of focus
groups, she found that the answers to the
two questions identified above were com-
plex and nuanced. The evidence suggests
that low-income individuals frequently
encounter legal problems, but even when
they recognize those problems as legal
(not always), they generally prefer to in-
volve neither lawyers nor courts. Cost is
often not the primary reason for their re-
luctance to turn to formal law.
8
Neither Sandefur’s research nor the
rcts on the effectiveness of different lev-
els of legal services support the idea that
legal services are worthless or that fund-
ing for legal services should be cut. This
rigorous research does suggest, however,
that standard narratives that exist in the
U.S. legal profession are distorted in ways
that matter.
The previous discussion suggests that
the new legal empiricism has already pro-
vided much to challenge assumptions
common in the U.S. legal profession.
The approach could also offer much in
the way of guidance for the profession’s
policy-makers, regulators, funders, re-
formers, and revolutionaries. Challenges
to accepted truths are helpful, but the
approach should also deliver construc-
tive ideas. Early indicators are that it
will be able to do so. Here are some ques-
tions about which, with adequate fund-
ing and with the political will among the
members of the legal profession, a new
legal empiricism could provide useful
guidance:
·
What would be the effects of partial de-
regulation of the U.S. legal profession?
Can limited licensed legal technicians,
or other kinds of nonlawyer legal pro-
fessionals, provide effective services
at a cost accessible to low-income in -
dividuals?
9
Can online legal-service providers like
LegalZoom, or free online legal-ser-
vice providers, or nonprofits that pro-
vide a hybrid of online and tradition-
al lawyer services provide an effec-
tive way for low-income individuals
to benefit from the justice system?
10
Would changing legal ownership
rules allowing lawyers, or unsuper-
vised nonlawyer legal professionals,
to work as salaried employees of cor-
porations with convenient locations
(think paralegals in offices at Wal-
mart) improve access for low-income
individuals and families?
11
·
What would be the effects of moving
certain disputes to online or app-based
adjudication?
12
·
Can algorithms and scoring systems, ad-
ministered by human beings or comput-
ers implementing artificial intelligence
programs, improve the functioning of
courts, legal-services offices, court ad-
ministrators, and other key actors with-
in the justice system, as is already occur-
ring in the medical profession?
13
·
Are there effective ways to divert indi-
viduals accused of crimes away from
the traditional criminal law system?
14
It is impossible to overstate the impor-
tance of these questions to the modern
justice system. The new legal empiricism
has much to offer.
If the new legal empiricism has already
exploded some of the myths that previ-
ously masqueraded as truths, and if it has
much to offer for the future, why has the
U.S. legal profession yet to embrace it, and
what can be done about the situation?
Because medicine and other disciplines
have incorporated rigorous empiricism
into their understandings of what counts
as true, it cannot be that the new legal
empiricism is inimical to the judgment-
based reasoning that the legal profession
offers in solving legal problems. Nor can
148 (1) Winter 2019 73
D. James
Greiner
it be that rigorous empiricism is incon-
sistent with professional ethics, legal or
otherwise. Again, the medical example
shows as much. Rigorous empiricism can
coexist with or alongside professional
judgment.
15
In the 1930s, when medicine began to
turn to rigorous empiricism (particular-
ly the
rct), medicine was less a science
than an individualized craft, especially as
it was practiced outside major cities and
teaching/research facilities.
16
And in this
period, published papers in both med-
icine and law began to make use of ran-
domization to conduct empirically rig-
orous studies, suggesting that the intel-
lectual foundation for transformation of
the legal system into an evidence-based
field was present then, just as it was in
medicine.
17
In prior work, Andrea Matthews and I
speculated that perhaps lawyers (and thus
judges, who in the United States are or-
dinarily former lawyers) resist rigorous
empiricism because 1) they are trained to
pursue goals that clients provide and their
thought processes are therefore funda-
mentally instrumental (in the service of
advocacy) as opposed to analytical; and
2) there may be social value to having law-
yers appear certain when they argue and
to having judges appear certain when they
make decisions, even when there is little
basis for that certainty, and to appear cer-
tain, lawyers and judges must convince
themselves that they are.
18
The first obser-
vation, if true, might make it hard for law-
yers and judges to embrace the new legal
empiricism because they are trained more
to argue than to analyze, and thus instinc-
tively seek persuasion rather than truth.
The second observation, if true, might
make it hard for lawyers and judges to em-
brace this approach because certainty in-
hibits a desire for rigorous investigation.
Neither observation/argument is close
to bulletproof. The duties of corporate
general counsels are less about advocacy
and more about strategic decision-making
and policy-making than those of, say,
courtroom litigators. Yet we see little if any
evidence of rigorous empiricism in corpo-
rate counsel offices, despite the supposed
existence of market forces that might put
a premium on using a new legal empiri-
cism to discover money-saving truths.
When Matthews and I provided our spec-
ulation, we stated that these two obser-
vations were likely insufficient to explain
fully the U.S. legal profession’s resistance
to evidence-based thinking.
Medicine’s partial turn to evidence-
based thinking reflected leadership shown
by particular members of the medical
profession; these leaders worked pri-
marily in urban teaching centers and had
strong connections to federal agencies.
19
The legal profession needs leaders who
can transform its thinking about what
counts as useful knowledge. Law schools
should create environments that intro-
duce students to the issues discussed here.
Legal academics aim to prepare the next
generation of leaders in the U.S. legal pro-
fession to lead. A crucial element of that
training is to teach about the need for,
and about how to work with researchers
to expand, the new legal empiricism.
74 Dædalus, the Journal of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences
The New Legal
Empiricism &
Its Application
to Access-to -
Justice Inquiries
endnotes
1
Thomas Pynchon, Gravity’s Rainbow (New York: Viking Press, 1973), 251.
2
Laura and John Arnold Foundation, Developing a National Model for Pretrial Risk Assessment (Hous-
ton and New York: Laura and John Arnold Foundation, 2013).
3
Figures to support the statements about oversubscription are on file with author, from a sur-
vey of 2014 cases in an eight-county area around Akron, Ohio. The statements regarding law-
yers’ focus on whether they can win are the result of conversations with legal aid attorneys
around the country, including in two Ohio locations.
4
Harry M. Marks, The Progress of Experiment: Science and Therapeutic Reform in the United States, 1900–
1990 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
5
See Laura and John Arnold Foundation, Developing a National Model for Pretrial Risk Assessment; and
Jon Kleinberg, Himabindu Lakkaraju, Jure Leskovec, et al., “Human Decisions and Machine
Predictions,” NBER Working Paper No. 23180 (Cambridge, Mass.: National Bureau of Eco-
nomic Research, 2017), http://www.nber.org/papers/w23180.
6
D. James Greiner and Cassandra Wolos Pattanayak, “Randomized Evaluation in Legal Assis-
tance: What Difference Does Representation (Offer and Actual Use) Make?” The Yale Law
Journal 121 (8) (2012): 2175–2179, note 154.
7
Ken Smith, Kelly Thayer, and Kathy Garwold, Final Report on the Assessment of Telephone-Based Legal
Assistance Provided by Pennsylvania Legal Aid Programs Funded under the Access to Justice Act (Traverse
City, Mich.: The Resource for Great Programs, 2012), https://www.paiolta.org/wp-content
/uploads/2014/05/Report-on-Telephone-Based-Legal-Assistance.pdf.
8
Rebecca L. Sandefur, “The Importance of Doing Nothing: Everyday Problems and Responses
of Inaction,” in Transforming Lives: Law and Social Process, ed. Pascoe Pleasence, Alexy Buck, Nigel
J. Balmer, et al. (Norwich, United Kingdom: The Stationary Office, 2007). See also Rebecca
L. Sandefur, “The Fulcrum Point of Equal Access to Justice: Legal and Non-Legal Institu-
tions of Remedy,” Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review 42 (4) (2009): 949.
9
See Washington State Bar Association, “Limited License Legal Technicians,” updated Septem-
b er 24, 2018, https://www.wsba.org/for-legal-professionals/join-the-legal-profession-in
-wa/limited-license-legal-technicians.
10
See LegalZoom, https://www.legalzoom.com/; and Upsolve, https://upsolve.org/.
11
See American Bar Association, “Rule 5.4: Professional Independence of a Lawyer,” https://
www.americanbar.org/groups/professional_responsibility/publications/model_rules_of_
professional_conduct/rule_5_4_professional_independence_of_a_lawyer.html.
12
See “Online Claims Service being Piloted in England and Wales,” Out-Law, April 10, 2018, https
://www.out-law.com/en/articles/2018/april/online-claims-service-piloted-england-wales/.
13
See Taylor Kubota, “Stanford Algorithm can Diagnose Pneumonia Better than Radiolo-
gists,” Stanford News, November 15, 2017, https://news.stanford.edu/2017/11/15/algorithm
-outperforms-radiologists-diagnosing-pneumonia/.
14
See Lone Star Justice Alliance, https://www.lonestarjusticealliance.org/.
15
D. James Greiner and Andrea Mathews, “Randomized Control Trials in the United States Le-
gal Profession,” Annual Review of Law and Social Science 12 (2016): 295.
16
Marks, The Progress of Experiment.
17
James Burns Amberson Jr., B. T. McMahon, and Max Piner, “A Clinical Trial of Sanocrysin
in Pulmonary Tuberculosis,” American Review of Tuberculosis 24 (1931): 401; and Frederick J.
Gaudet, George S. Harris, and Charles W. St. John, “Individual Differences in the Sentenc-
ing Tendencies of Judges,” Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 23 (5) (1933).
18
Greiner and Matthews, “Randomized Control Trials in the United States Legal Profession.”
19
Marks, The Progress of Experiment.