.*5&12*38/'&.31",,/1*%" .*5&12*38/'&.31",,/1*%"



)&&"3)&.",38&#"3&1*3*$",7"-*."3*/./'3)&/1",)&&"3)&.",38&#"3&1*3*$",7"-*."3*/./'3)&/1",
423*:$"3*/.2'/1"0*3",4.*2)-&.3423*:$"3*/.2'/1"0*3",4.*2)-&.3
!)*3,&8"..
.*5&12*38/'&.31",,/1*%"
"13/'3)&)*,/2/0)8/--/.2
*.%2*-*,"16/1+2"3)330223"12,*#1"184$'&%4)/./123)&2&2
.*5&12*38/'&.31",,/1*%"*#1"1*&2)330,*#1"184$'&%4
)*20&.$$&22*2#1/4()33/8/4'/1'1&&".%/0&."$$&22#83)"2#&&."$$&03&%'/1*.$,42*/.*.
#8"."43)/1*9&%"%-*.*231"3/1/'/1-/1&*.'/1-"3*/.0,&"2&$/.3"$34$'&%4
&$/--&.%&%*3"3*/.&$/--&.%&%*3"3*/.
"..!)*3,&8)&&"3)&.",38&#"3&1*3*$",7"-*."3*/./'3)&/1",423*:$"3*/.2'/1"0*3",
4.*2)-&.3


)330223"12,*#1"184$'&%4)/./123)&2&2
THE DEATH PENALTY DEBATE:
A CRITICAL EXAMINATION OF THE MORAL JUSTIFICATIONS FOR
CAPITAL PUNISHMENT
by
WHITLEY G. MANN
A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements
for the Honors in the Major Program in Philosophy
in the College of Arts and Humanities
and in The Burnett Honors College
at the University of Central Florida
Orlando, Florida
Spring Term 2015
Thesis Chair: Dr. Harry Coverston
ii"
"
ABSTRACT
Capital punishment is a forceful moral issue that is frequently overlooked. This is
possibly due to the reverence many have toward the rule of law or a passive acceptance
of the status quo. In this thesis I will begin with a discussion of context to the topic of the
death penalty in order to address potential biases. Then I examine not only the ethical
merit of the death penalty but the foundational justifications for a system of criminal
justice to show that the special relationship between the state and its citizens does not
lend itself to or allow for the instantiation of the death penalty.
I look first to several theories of punishment selecting the most viable theory in
order to make the most plausible case in favor of the death penalty. From there I establish
that there is some intuitive merit to the notion that the vicious deserve unhappiness and
see how far that intuition might extend. In this section I examine the merits and demerits
of Kantian retributivism in order to address the many intricate ethical and political issues
involved in the death penalty debate. I’ve chosen the Kantian ethical framework because
of the nuance with which many of the problems of retribution are solved. Kant insets the
enlightenment principles into his moral framework and provides reasoned explanations
for there insistence, as such his work provides a background from which I will work
through details and resolve contradictions.
I will then make an argument for the moral personhood of the state and sketch the
special relationship it has to its citizens. Finally I will offer a system that incorporates the
ideas developed in the previous sections and gives a practical answer to the death penalty
debate. It is my ultimate argument that there is no absolute ban on the death penalty,
possibly even some intuitive merit to the scheme, but ultimately many moral limitations
iii"
"
on its implementation.
iv"
"
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
I wish to thank my committee Dr. Harry Coverston, Dr. Lin Huff-Corzine, and
Dr. Stephen McFarlane for their time, advice, and encouragement. I would like to
especially thank to Dr. Coverston for guiding me through and always having faith in me,
I couldn’t have done it without you. I would also like to thank Dr. Travis Rodgers for
inspiring me to pursue philosophy and for all his help on my thesis. Finally, thank you to
Denise Crisafi for all of your patience.
!
v"
"
TABLE OF CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION .............................................................................................................. 1
CONTEXT OF THE DEATH PENALTY DEBATE ........................................................ 3
JUSTIFICATIONS ............................................................................................................. 6
RESTITUTION".............................................................................................................................................."8"
DETERRENCE"..........................................................................................................................................."12"
RETRIBUTION".........................................................................................................................................."17"
KANTIAN"RETRIBUTIVISM"................................................................................................................."20"
THE STATE ..................................................................................................................... 28
HIERARCHY OF PUNISHMENT .................................................................................. 38
CONCLUSION ................................................................................................................. 44
WORKS CITED ............................................................................................................... 46
1"
"
INTRODUCTION
For most people the death penalty debate is distant and theoretical. One of the
arguments against even engaging this discussion is that such theoretical debate is useless
because no one truly knows what their intuitions would be in such a confusing and
painful situation. When I was fifteen a family friend was convicted of a triple homicide
and I still can’t say I have clear intuitions about the situation. On the one hand I see a
monster that shot a six-year-old girl at point blank range and on the other I see the father
of a disabled son who attended the family Christmas Eve party each year. His mother,
who declined to testify in court, explained to me that while she would always love him
she truly believed her son deserved to die. The sentiments of the victim’s family ranged
from pleas to end the violence to a stated desire to be the one to take Justin’s life. August
2009 Justin Heyne was sentenced to be executed by lethal injection in 2015.
1
It is easy for most people to imagine murderers, especially those whose crime is
considered heinous, as truly evil people deserving of death but the chances are that they
are people who are capable of good and bad. At trial, the defense brought up the fact that
Justin had an I.Q. of 88 and a cocktail of mental disorders and brain damage. They also
brought up the fact that Justin was good to his disabled son and at the sentencing trial
family and teachers told anecdotes of Justin giving his coat to a homeless man and
defending weaker kids at school. The prosecutor demonstrated that Ivory, the 6-year-old
girl, was tugging on Justin’s shorts and was shot after her parents were incapacitated
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
1
"JUSTIN CURTIS HEYNE vs. STATE OF FLORIDA.
2"
"
(thus diminishing any chance the murder was an accident in self-defense.) Probably the
most sickening part of the trial was when the prosecution explained that the coroner
found that Ivory had been slapped before her death so hard that the blood vessels in face
burst.
This is not necessarily to say that that a crime of this nature begets its own
punishment nor is it to say that no one, by right of his or her humanity, is deserving of
death. The point I’m trying to make is that if one is going to participate in this discussion
as an impartial observer, they cannot simply write off the humanity of the criminal. They
must ignore surface inclinations to dismiss a person altogether as a monster and at the
very least fully consider the humanity of the criminal and what making the decision to
end a persons life truly means.
3"
"
CONTEXT OF THE DEATH PENALTY DEBATE
In Plato’s Apology Socrates describes why he feels he must follow the ruling of
the jury and take his own life. Since then philosophers have examined the morality and
policy of the death penalty, though more frequently than not it was used as an example to
elucidate a larger picture of justice rather than a set piece in its own right.
2
Even though
the death penalty was frequently implemented for petty theft until well into the 1700’s,
most of the scholarly writing focused on the execution of murderers and usually revolved
around retributive or utilitarian considerations. Many philosophers insisted on the
implementation of capital punishment, from Hobbes and Montesquieu to Kant and Mill,
which seems in direct contrast to the idea of human dignity. The concept that humanity
has some inherent value is one of the least controversial premises in post-enlightenment
philosophy.
Though it is possible to judge an argument solely on its merit and not its context,
it is possible that entrenched tradition associated with the death penalty may have skewed
the intuitions of a great many thinkers and may still continue to do so. When an
institution permeates a society it is difficult to test its negation. The death penalty is often
defended as a necessity of justice and yet it is a relic of some of the most unjust periods
in human history. It is much easier to fabricate a defense of a millennia old tradition than
to confront the brutality of one’s own inclinations.
“Throughout the greater part of human history punishment was not
imposed because one held the wrongdoer responsible for his deed, thus not on the
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
2
Bedau “Bentham's Utilitarian Critique of the Death Penaltypg 1036, (1983)
4"
"
presupposition that only the guilty one should be punished: rather, as parents still
punish their children, from anger at some harm or injury, vented on the one who
caused it—but this anger is held in check and modified by the idea that every
injury has its equivalent and can actually be paid back, even if only through the
pain of the culprit. And whence did this primeval, deeply rooted, perhaps by now
ineradicable idea draw its power—this idea of an equivalence between injury and
pain? … in the contractual relationship between creditor and debtor, which is as
old as the idea of "legal subjects" and in turn points back to the fundamental
forms of buying, selling, barter, trade, and traffic.”
3
Obviously Nietzsche had his own ideas about how to do philosophy, but there is
something commonsensical about this line of reasoning. It seems reasonable, knowing
what we do about the development of the human species, that indeed the strongest of a
group was able to lash out at whomever he or she pleased and that practice evolved
alongside societies and now manifests in the idea of retributive justice. But whether or
not this is an accurate anthropological picture of the development of punishment
throughout the ages, it provides an argument in favor of analyzing the debate under a new
framework.
With the enlightenment principles (such as freedom, equality, rights, justice, and
the value of human life) in mind, the standard for successfully arguing in favor of capital
punishment is very high because taking a human life violates every one of the previous
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
3
Nietzsche On the Genealogy of Morals” pg 471,(1969)
5"
"
principles. In order to advocate the death penalty one must develop a theory of justice
that establishes a value to be gained by executions that outweighs the significant costs.
The chief ways of achieving this have been to point either to the guilt of the offender or
the benefit to society. If we point to the guilt of the offender we must justify why only the
death penalty is appropriate and necessary. If we point to the benefit to society we must
justify why the benefit to society supersedes the grave consequences to the individual.
Further, in order to justify the death penalty we must rule out any other considerations
that may be overriding, such as an alternative theory of justice or otherwise unconsidered
societal side effects.
6"
"
JUSTIFICATIONS
As is the case with any form of argumentation if one does not accept the
foundational principle upon which the argument is premised all further discussion is
moot. In the death penalty debate the foundational principle is a theory of justice and in
particular a theory of punishment. There are many theories and variations on those
theories and it would be impossible to attempt to address them all in one body of work. I
will give a brief explanation of Restitution (or Restorative Justice) and Deterrence and
discuss the reasons they are not currently viable justifications for the death penalty.
Ultimately I will focus on Retribution because I believe it presents a schema in which one
can reasonably determine whether a person deserves death. Because Kant’s ethical theory
proceeds from the notion of human dignity I will frame the argument going forward on
that system in order to give a reasonable perspective in favor of practical retribution.
Because Kant’s theory of punishment relies heavily on his political theory and
because punishment in general is linked to the state I will discuss the state’s role as a
moral actor. With emphasis on the enlightenment principles of human dignity, objective
morality, and the value of life I will elaborate on Kant’s metaphysics of justice as well as
some elements of his moral theory as a whole in order to come to a conclusion about the
death penalty. Finally I will discuss a type of punishment theory that involves retributive
judgments of severity (in the form of a hierarchy of punishments), deterrent motivations,
and limitations on who can be punished (namely those who have committed a crime).
Though his arguments lead to a retributive view of punishment, Immanuel Kant
provides an interesting blend of elements when framing the execution of his ideal
7"
"
criminal justice system. While the severity and amount of punishment are determined by
purely retributive consideration, Kant allows for deterrent considerations in determining
the manner of punishment. It may very well be the case that no single theory will provide
a satisfactory answer to the death penalty debate and instead elements from each of the
theories will be necessary to formulate an answer that adheres to the notion of human
dignity. Kant achieves this goal to a large degree but there are still instances of
contradiction in his work. In no uncertain terms Kant’s moral theory supports capital
punishment and the rule of law but I will discuss how this is one of the areas of
disjunction in his work.
8"
"
RESTITUTION
Restitution is a relatively recent theory and is based on rights such that, if A burns
down B’s house then A has violated B’s right to his or her property and B is faced with
the loss of a house and the inconveniences that follow. Thus A has taken from B and
created a deficit. In the context of Restitution, a right can be described as a security in
one’s person or property that he or she has free and unencumbered use of, provided that
use is not itself violating another person’s rights. A violation results in an unjust
distribution of entitlement leading to a right in the victim to remedy the imbalance up to
the maximum reparation, which would be equivalent to the damage caused by the crime.
This imbalance can be understood as a debt incurred by the offender to the victim.
By violating the right of the victim the perpetrator has opened him/herself up to
be similarly treated. The mechanism for this is the caveat introduced in the initial
explanation of rights, namely that one only has uninterrupted rights in so far as he or she
does not use that right to harm others. Restitution takes this to mean that because the
offender created the deficit they have the responsibility to repay it. Reparations may take
the form of money or services paid to the victim of a crime by the perpetrator of the
crime in order to remedy a rights violation. In this theory justice consists of the offender
making right their wrong but in what way could execution reasonably be considered
righting a wrong?
In the example of the death penalty, there is no benefit to the victim other than the
fruition of vengeance, which is an ill-fitting aim of justice. For instance if there is no
9"
"
physical or material harm to a victim merely insult or humiliation, that victim would be
entitled to demand the perpetrator suffer insult in return. While we may agree that the
good deserve happiness and the evil unhappiness, the force of this claim is lost when the
sentence is determined by the whim of the victim. Restitution has admittedly takes the
psychological affect of the victims into account. More over since, according to
Restitution, the motives of the perpetrator needn’t be examined the punishment be for am
unintended insult would be as great as that of an intended insult if it were felt as deeply
by the victim (for lack of a better word). If vengeance were to be taken seriously in
restitution the results would certainly not reflect our intuitions about justice.
Further if we were to imagine a response to this problem that was suitably
satisfying there is still the troubling issue of the vast degree of variation that is possible in
a system of Restitution. Because the system of Restitution is primarily focused on the
victim, the victim ultimately gets to decide the fate of the criminal, from full pardon up
unto the full weight of the damages of their crime. Restitution is an easy calculation in
the realm of violations to rights of property but it becomes more complicated when it is
applied to violations of rights to personal security. Property can easily be measured by
quantitative means and thus repaid in kind by a transfer of monies but bodily damage is a
qualitative offense and thus is not so easily translated. While the victim is not the sole
consideration in sentencing they play a substantial role.
For instance the extent to which the crime emotionally affects the victim is
accounted for, even if the affect is purely the result of disposition. If the victim is inclined
toward anger a transgression against him will affect them more powerfully than if it were
10"
"
directed toward a victim who was more disposed to composure and thus the former
would result in greater damages. Further in terms of a violations of the rights of a person
a victim may choose not to receive any compensation at all due to the legitimate desire
not to further their pain by involving themselves with the source of their distress. The
result of considering the preference of the victim is a wide range of possible punishments
for the same or similar crimes.
This leads to concerns about the practical application of a restorative theory of
justice. Restorative justice requires a system to arbitrate disputes in a way that will result
in a large variation of consequences. When such variation can sway from no
consequences to execution based heavily and admittedly on a person’s disposition, the
system is likely to be viewed as arbitrary by the very people it is charged with mediating.
In the current judicial system, which may in fact be effected by a group of people’s
disposition, this sort of influence is expressly avoided where possible. If an occasion
arises where the public conception of a particular judgment is that it is being levied due
solely or in large part to a disposition instead of properly processed law or judgments
about the just response to the situation then the public has a grounds to dispute the
decision or practice.
For instance, this is not necessarily the case in restitution but it is certainly
vulnerable to this concern, the recent data uncovering the skewed sentencing practices
toward certain races and racial composition of crimes. Where African Americans were
sentenced to death at a much higher rate than their stake in the population and African
American crimes against Caucasians were punished much more severely than the reverse.
11"
"
In the current system this was outraged to the point of repealing the entire practice of the
death penalty for a number of years, but victims were more strongly affected by one race
due to prejudices that would be a legitimate concern in restorative justice.
4
When trust in an official system is undercut there is a risk for informal systems to
rise in popularity. These systems may seem more legitimate to the population than the
current system while resulting in horrible consequences. For instance the use of religious
council in Afghanistan, rising in popularity due to mistrust of a corrupted system, have
led to the marriages of infants to grown men to settle monetary debt among other things.
5
Ambiguity in punishment is likely to lead to an unstable system and thus in order to
maintain a system of justice that will be respected and therefore have the ability to supply
any restoration what so ever there needs to be a standard that is generally agreed upon.
If we have a system that only passingly considers the preferences of the victim
but hold strong to one consistent principle then A) we must decide what that principle
must be and B) a system with a central principle other than the restoration of the victim’s
damages is a system other than restitution. Also, if we include in this system an
exemption for vengeance sought by the victim the system begins to look like Retribution
rather than Restitution. Retribution also has to contend with criticisms regarding
ambiguity in application but it is better equipped to address such claims due to its static
underlying principle.
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
4
The Death Penalty Information Center “Racial Disparities in Federal Death Penalty
Prosecutions(1994)
5
United Nations Development Program “Informal Justice Systems” (2012)
12"
"
DETERRENCE
The deterrence theory of punishment is at the same time easily accessible and
utterly nebulous. It is generally the prima facie justification for punishment, possibly
because it mirrors our intuitions about self-defense: if someone is attacking you it is
necessary that you make them stop. In the same way if someone is attacking the
community it is imperative that the authority of that community makes them stop.
This theory begins to become problematic when it extends this line of reasoning to
the deterrence of a crime before it is committed, specifically before it is known to be a
threat. In this case the deterrence theory of punishment devolves into a blanket statement
amounting to “punishment is justified if is deters future crime.” This devolves because it
is entirely unspecific: How much punishment is justified? What crimes justify what
measures of deterrence? What constitutes a punishment? To what degree should a society
aim to deter (i.e. wholly, maximally, maximally with the constraints of rights, etc.)?
To this end the deterrence theory of punishment must be paired with a set of
societal values or a moral theory. While the idea that we should prevent pain and
hardship where possible is relatively uncontroversial, the various ways of specifically
formulating that general claim into a plan of action is wrought with complications that at
least require careful consideration.
Utilitarianism is the most frequently cited moral theory that applies a deterrent
justification of punishment. One of the biggest criticisms of the utilitarian moral theory is
that it neglects the individual and ignores the concept of human dignity. This criticism is
the result of a calculus central to Utilitarian moral theory that can be summarized as “the
13"
"
greatest happiness for the greatest number.” Under this calculation, who benefits from the
action – and at whose expense that benefit is derived - is not important and thus a great
deal of injustice and brutality can be justified by the pleasure of the perpetrator.
Still, the deterrence theory of punishment is not inextricably linked to Utilitarianism
and a critique of one is not necessarily a critique of the other. Deterrence could be framed
around a theory of rights, namely that one has a right to their own body and property so
far as they do not use that right to violate the rights of others. This formulation of right
would establish both a need for protection and a means to justify violating this protection
to pursue punishment (because under this conception one only has a right in so far as they
are not using that right to violate the rights of others). Because this theory will ultimately
not be the topic of discussion I will not develop an in depth theory and will instead move
forward with the minimum theory of rights needed to discuss rights based deterrence as a
possible theory.
Thus, under utilitarian theory the idea of deterring future crime in order to
effectively protect the rights of all may be used as a justification for punishment. Here the
concept of retribution isn’t necessary because the focus is not righting a wrong but
preventing future wrongs. It could conceivably be the case that public announcements of
laws and well known follow through is the best way to convince someone on the brink of
committing a crime not to go through with the action.
6
We may even add the caveat that
the violation one commits is the limit to which one can be punished. Ignoring for the
moment the possibility of mistaken convictions, which is truly an issue with punishment
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
6
"classical"school"of"punishment""
14"
"
no matter what it’s justification, there is one issue left standing with the concept of
deterrence, namely does punishment actually deter future crime? This may seem like an
obvious point, or maybe begging of the question ‘why propose a theory of deterrence if
punishment doesn’t deter crime?’ But accurate data on such a sensitive and large-scale
question is hard to acquire. For example there is no naturally occurring control group and
it is morally impermissible to arbitrarily assign the death penalty to some and not to
others. Further measuring the actually rather than reported rate of deterrence in a
population would involve tracking a statistically significant number of people in two
areas, one randomly assigned the death penalty and the other the control, before these
citizens ever committed a crime.
There is much philosophical rousing into the nature of man, for instance John
Stuart Mill
7
states that due to the unique nature of man the punishment of death is both
more merciful than a life sentence and the most feared of all punishments making it a
perfect utilitarian punishment because it minimizes the suffering of the victim while
maximizing the deterrence effect netting the most over all happiness.
Hugo Adam Bedau
8
, a Harvard professor of philosophy, on the other hand argues that
due to the unique nature of man the idea of deterrence, specifically in the case of the
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
7
John Stuart Mill “Speech in favor of Capital Punishment” (2015)
8
In “The Case Against the Death Penalty” Bedau states “Persons who commit murder and other
crimes of personal violence either premeditate them or they do not. If the crime is premeditated,
the criminal ordinarily concentrates on escaping detection, arrest, and conviction. The threat of
even the severest punishment will not deter those who expect to escape detection and arrest. If the
crime is not premeditated, then it is impossible to imagine how the threat of any punishment
could deter it. Most capital crimes are committed during moments of great emotional stress or
under the influence of drugs or alcohol, when logical thinking has been suspended. Impulsive or
expressive violence is inflicted by persons heedless of the consequences to themselves as well as
to others.”
15"
"
death penalty, is logically unsound. He argues that a crime is either premeditated or not,
if it is premeditated then the focus of the criminal is not to be caught at all and if the
crime is not premeditated there is no consideration to the consequences no matter what
they may be.
While these are interesting and in some way appealing to common sense, the
modern advancements in such technology have shown just how difficult decisive
statistics on the matter can be to produce. Experts are torn on the matter and data has
revealed everything from a marked reduction in homicide to a marked increase in
homicides as a result of the death penalty. I will cite sources here
9
to note the controversy
but the evidence is clear that there is no decided fact of the matter among the experts. As
such the matter remains unresolved. In the lack of conclusive evidence on the matter
leaves a deterrence justification for the death penalty a possibility for which little can be
said until further developments can be made.
Until such a development there is reason to err on the side of abolition. Several
authors, such as Jeffery Reinman
10
and Hugo Adam Bedau
11
, have proposed an
expansion on Caesar Baccaria’s idea that the death penalty rather than saving lives
actually degrades the societal respect for human life and thus increases the rate of
violence. This seems to fall in league with the ponderings of the earlier mentioned
philosopher, but if there is a chance not only that executing criminals results in no gain to
society but that the abolition of the death penalty could save lives then the moral
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
9
Donohue Uses and Abuses of Empirical Evidence in the Death Penalty Debate” pg 791 (2015)
10
Reiman “Justice, Civilization, and the Death Penalty: Answering van den Haag” pg 120-28
(1985)
11
Bedau “The Case Against the Death Penalty” (2015)
16"
"
community has a greater responsibility to side in favor of caution than to rely on one of
many common sense proposals being offered.
17"
"
RETRIBUTION
Having provided an explanation for and ultimately a dismissal of the other major
theories of punishment I will focus on retribution for the rest of this thesis. Retribution is
less susceptible to the criticisms of the other punishment theories because it is based on
an idea that is intuitively sound: the virtuous deserve to be happy and the vicious deserve
to be unhappy. It is difficult to see how that could be argued against in terms of ideal
justice, but retribution implies a sort of proportionality in practice. The stipulation that
punishment be proportionate to the crime causes one major point of confusion namely the
question: what does proportionality entail? I will discuss the groundwork for retribution
generally and move toward a specific formulation.
In both academic circles and popular consensus Retribution is becoming a more
common moral justification for capital punishment. Intuitions are swaying from the
severity of a numerical calculus to the more malleable abstracts of desert and
responsibility. Many outside the philosophical community may not know they are using
this sort of justification and in fact when named it is not an uncommon occurrence that
retribution is mistaken for retaliation. While the two share some key components, namely
their reciprocity, they are markedly different in emphasis. Retaliation is the act of
harming someone because they have harmed you. Retribution is a punishment levied
against someone because they have done something wrong. The emphasis of Retaliation
is to return some hardship while the emphasis of retribution is to right a wrong.
With this in mind there are still several important ambiguities surrounding
Retribution. First we must establish that a given punishment is in fact the correct
18"
"
response to a given crime. Many theories accomplish this by simply applying a rule of
equilibrium, for every crime there must be a punishment of equal effect. But there are
other schools of thought that focus more heavily on the aspects of Retribution that limit
the severity of a possible punishment rather than demand the equality of action and
reaction.
Even if we can establish what constitutes just deserts and the existence of a
necessity to impose responsibility on moral agents, what is the mechanism that demands
a certain group of agents carries out the punishment? If that theory of just deserts falls in
line with a moral equilibrium the body charged with balancing the equation (because if
this is the case it is equally important to reward good acts as it is to punish bad acts)
would necessarily be a universal karmic force. Unfortunately such power is yet unknown
to humanity and we must settle for a criminal justice system.
While most justice systems throughout the world are developed with the express
purpose of minimizing the convictions of innocent people and the escape of guilty
people, such events continue to take place at an alarming rate. I am hesitant to throw the
baby out with the bath water but when one seeks to have perfect equilibrium such
mistakes seem incredibly damaging to the whole system. If the retributive system is
designed to balance the scales of justice wrongful convictions exacerbate the problems
instead of championing the cause
While it is true that the imperfections of humanity will have an effect on all
justifications of punishment it is uniquely a problem for Retribution. In the utilitarian
system such seeming mistakes can be justified by the overall satisfaction society received
19"
"
from the idea that they have a working justice system. In Restitution the goal of the
system is not to right wrongs but to compensate victims. Therefore in a system of
Restitution wrongful convictions, while tragic, do not totally undermine the goal of the
system as a whole as they do in the case of a Retributive system.
One problem with the requirement for equality is that it would necessitate
reciprocity for good behavior as well and whatever force drives one body to punish
would propel, if not the same group, another body to reward. But this is not worked into
many formulations of retribution and certainly not in the systems currently seen. A
possible counter argument for this point may be that controlling people’s bad behaviors
keeps others safe so there is impetus for outsiders to involve themselves. First this
reasoning could just as easily apply to good behavior such as saving others from peril,
helping others with potentially hazardous tasks, or even in a more material sense giving
financial advice. Second this type of reasoning should not matter in a purely Retributive
system because controlling behavior is not the aim of Retribution.
Since there are a number of ways to frame a retributive system I will start with the
Kantian perspective and proceed from there. Kant is a viable candidate because he begins
with several of the most universally appreciated concepts (some of which he was first to
articulate) such as: equality among all people, negative rights, and the dignity of man.
From these concepts Kant formulates a theory of retribution designed to respect the
dignity of man on both counts, that of the victim and that of the culprit. It is both because
of its recent popularity and the abstract principles that underlie retributive theory that I
will move forward with it as the preferred theory of justice.
20"
"
KANTIAN RETRIBUTIVISM
Kant’s moral theory is in many ways reflective of his time. This may come as no
surprise to those who are familiar with his method but Kant did not seek to alter traditions
only to explain them in a coherent and intuitive way. This is the same methodology that
led to his Copernican revolution in Philosophy of Mind. The result in Kant’s moral
theory is that, while the rationale behind it all may be innovative, what is morally
permissible is ultimately inline with the Euro-Christian culture of his time. As culture has
adapted, it is now the rationale that stands and is so widely appreciated. Thus there is a
strange rift between the foundational principles that Kant sets forth (equality to all, duty
not only to oneself but to other, the value of human life) and the severe nature of his
theory of punishment.
Kant was novel in his idea that rationality could motivate one to action and it is in
this idea that Kant formulates moral personhood. For Kant freedom is more than a lack of
obstacles but the power of causal self-determination. Thus when he says “moral
personality is nothing more than the freedom of a rational being under moral laws”
12
he
means that moral personality, or the character of a specific agent’s duties and
relationships, is the ability to act in complete independence of any causes other than
one’s own reason. To be free therefore is to be morally responsible. A Person, with a
moral personality, is thus “subject to no laws other than those that he gives himself
(either alone or at least with others at the same time).”
13
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
12
Ladd The Metaphysical Elements of Justice” pg17, (1999)
13
Ibid.
21"
"
Persons thus cannot be mere things because they possess the capacity to create
their own ends. What has no true equivalent cannot have a price, because a moral agent
has their own ends they must be considered an end in themselves and so there is no true
equivalent. Thus human life is beyond all worth.
14
Yet Kant also claims “if one has committed murder, he must die.”
15
So how does
Kant’s theory of punishment unfold to this conclusion? Kant’s theory of the justification
is engaging because it attempts not only compatibility with the idea of human dignity but
in fact proceeds directly from that premise. This is not to say that Kant’s formulation is
entirely successful or even that it aims to be compatible with every variation on the
concept of human dignity.
The basic tenant of retributive theory is the offender, in committing a crime,
deserves a punishment. Kant is one of the best-known retributive proponents of the death
penalty. His argument is roughly formulated as: in intentionally causing the death of an
innocent person (i.e. not the execution of a murderer) the murderer has rendered himself
deserving of death.
16
An important thing to note here is that Kant draws a very clear line;
someone may only be punished because they willed a punishable act. A person’s innate
moral personality protects them from being used as a means to an end, whether that end
is to his benefit or the benefit of society.
This means any supplementary justification of punishment, such as reforming the
criminal or deterring future crime and thus minimizing the harm to society, may only be
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
14
Groundwork mm 53
15
Ladd Metaphysical Elements of Justice” Pg139
16
Ladd “E on the right to punish and grant clemency” 6:333
22"
"
an added benefit. Such justifications are not sufficient to authorize the violation of one’s
dignity but may be considered by the state after the guilty of the culprit has been
determined. For Kant, justice ceases to be justice when it can be bought at any price
whatsoever. That is to say that the full sentencing force must rely entirely on the principle
of retribution that one is only punished because they are guilty and thus the punishment
must be reflective of the crime.
Kant, like a great many philosophers, has a separate moral and political theory.
The state plays a particularly important role in Kant’s argument because according to him
without a state one cannot have true freedom and thus one cannot have moral personality.
Kant writes that in a state of nature there can be no justice because there is no law and
thus it is a moral offense to break a law even if the law would otherwise carry no moral
weight.
One important point that arises from Kant’s legal theory is the characteristic of
equality in justice. As Kant put it “justice is measured in the position of the needle on the
scale of justice.” This is true of any crime and is best demonstrated by Kant’s description
of theft, “when you steal from someone, you steal from yourself.”
17
In stealing from a
member of the political community you deprive all the members of that community the
security of their possessions, and so you deprive yourself any possible security in your
own possessions. Kant’s formulation of the state provides interesting insight into how
this may follow. If we take for granted that in the absence of enforced law one can have
no freedom it follows that a violation of the law would infringe on the freedom of the
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
17
Ladd pg138
23"
"
community under the law. Because you have no security in your possessions “you have
nothing and can acquire nothing” so the state must provide for you. But, Kant argues,
they will not do so free of charge and this is where the state’s discretion to send a person
to jail or debtor’s prison stems from.
Kant argues that sending someone to jail for the crime of theft may in fact be
reflective of and equal to the crime. This is because he does not prescribe equality in act
but in effect, the effect of the punishment must be equal to the crime. In number of
instances simply retaliating in kind does not capture the full force of the crime. For
instance if I am a professional piano player and you break my wrist I may no longer be
able to make a living, so if your wrist is broken in return and it causes only discomfort
the effect of the crime is not reflected. The suggestion here is that we use the effect of the
original crime to balance the scale of justice, will the full and accurate force of the crime
committed, rather than simply returning the action. In some ways this falls into the same
trap deterrence theory finds itself in: some of the empirical evidence necessary for this
ideal to be practically implemented is too difficult to attain or simply impossible to
predict. This means that it is possible that Kant miscalculated the difference in effect of
the death penalty and life in prison.
Further Kant points out that since this caveat dismisses the need for exact
retaliation the state may, as it sees fit, alter the punishment to meet the needs of the state
so long as it falls with the boundaries just established. Kant writes after guilt has been
established the state should “punish in such a way that security be obtained.” This means
that, for instance, the arrest and sentencing records can be publicized after each criminal
24"
"
has gotten their due process in order to dissuade future criminal with the threat of a
similar fate. Alternatively if one commits a particularly heinous or dreadful crime their
punishment may be made public to deter future crime or ease public anxiety about the
crimes. The argument made is that either way the morally correct action is to punish a
criminal in a way reflective of their crime, if the state can use that punishment to their
benefit then no harm done.
But if the proper punishment is not set in stone in the moment after the crime is
committed then why is Kant so strict on murder necessitating capital punishment. In the
first part of the metaphysical elements of justice Kant writes of the death penalty
“Even if a civil society resolved to dissolve itself with the consent of all its
members- as might be supposed in the case of a people inhabiting an island resolving to
separate and scatter themselves throughout the whole world- the last murderer lying in
the prison ought to be executed before the resolution was carried out. This ought to be
done in order that every one may realize the desert of his deeds, and that blood-guiltiness
may not remain upon the people; for otherwise they might all be regarded as
participators in the murder as a public violation of justice.”
18
Why does Kant have such harsh words for those who seek to find a justification
for the abolition of the death penalty? Kant’s reasoning is that death shares no similarities
with life (no matter how awful that life may be) hence there is no likeness between
murder and any punishment other than death. Due to the fundamental difference between
the two, life can never be equal to death, even in the more diluted sense previously
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
18
Ladd pg140
25"
"
mentioned, and thus can never satisfy justice. For Kant failing to implement justice is a
grave issue because when we let justice go “there is no longer any value in human
beings’ living on earth.”
Yet Kant argues that while killing an innocent man is a mistake, letting a guilty
man go free is a greater affront to justice. In Kant’s view failing to punish a guilty person
has more moral gravity than executing an innocent person because when we fail to punish
those who commit a crime we let justice go and, according to Kant, when we let justice
go “there is no longer any value in human beings’ living on earth.”
19
Isn’t a state fabricated injustice just as weighty, if not more, than the failure to
execute an innocent man? One may argue that this is true of all punishment, and that if
we are to follow this logic to it natural end there would be no justification for any
punishment because a system of justice is just as likely to make a mistake in
imprisonment as they are to mistakenly execute someone. The important thing to
remember in regard to this point is the irrevocability of death. If a state imprisons
someone for life and 20 years into the sentence it is discovered by way of DNA evidence
the convict is not guilty then the convict can be released, his honor restored, and
reparations from the state can begin to be made. If a man is executed and later found to
be innocent there is no chance for reparations. While monetary reparations cannot fully
repay lost time and freedom, there is a point at which the harm can be stopped and an
attempt to recover losses can be made.
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
19
Ladd pg37
26"
"
Further in the case of a wrongful conviction that is not overturned there is a
second injustice: the lack of conviction of the true criminal. In this case justice is not
satisfied and it is violated at the same time. Practically speaking the presence of a living
prisoner advocating their innocence at the least provides some emphasis for further
inquiry into the crime. In such a case there is some chance that the wrong may be righted
and the guilty convicted. One may argue that a system of criminal justice can be more or
less accurate but barring an omniscient entity there will always be some mistakes.
This critique poses the question, if the goal is to right moral wrong and the state
of things is such that humanity is incapable of doing this perfectly and thus the very
system designed to correct injustice is perpetuating injustice then are we left with unjust
death? Kant wrote that to avoid murder was a perfect duty. In his opposition to
utilitarianism Kant states that to take one innocent life to save others is not morally right
action. The morality of an action depends on the action itself and not the consequences.
According to Kant’s the idea that we must treat humanity as an end in itself is
inconsistent with murder, even the murder of oneself. In the groundwork for the
metaphysics of moral Kant states “I cannot, therefore, dispose in any way of a man in my
own person so as to mutilate him, to damage or kill him.”
We must ask ourselves if the goal of moral certitude in acute accuracy of
retaliation is worth even one innocent life. How great must the divide be between life and
death that a life of imprisonment is in no way approaching equivalence to death? John
Stuart Mill believed the death penalty should be implemented not because it was more
27"
"
severe but because it was most merciful. In his address to parliament
20
Mill argues that
the human brain tricks itself into the fear of death because it is unknown, while in fact a
life of imprisonment is far worse. It is true that life and death are dissimilar but so is
thievery and imprisonment. It is difficult to argue against the intrinsic value of the
virtuous deserving happiness and the vicious deserving unhappiness but if the question is
“should there be a system that returns most crimes but if in so doing it causes further
irreparable injustice?” then an imperfectly balanced punishment, in the form of life
sentences, seems the morally permissible answer.
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
20
Mill “Speech in Favor of Capital Punishment”
28"
"
THE STATE
The question of the state and the role of the punisher introduce a new element into
the debate. There is a duty not to harm others in respecting them as an end in themselves
and not as merely a means. Since, as such, it is morally impermissible to kill, in what way
does the guilt of the culprit alter that duty?
Surely we cannot say that harming another person is punishment if the agent responsible
for the harm is unaware of the guilt of their victim. This implies a distinction between the
mere guilt of the recipient of punishment and the moral certitude of the punisher. For
instance, we can imagine a situation where a serial killer executes a pedophile unaware of
the pedophilic nature of his victim. In such a case the guilt of the victim does not alter the
serial killer’s duty not to harm others and would not be considered a punishment for the
pedophiles crimes. Though some may consider the result of the circumstances (i.e. the
death of the pedophile) just, the serial killer is still morally blameworthy for their actions.
When an established criminal justice system pursues punishment there is no such
ignorance of the fact, the state acts on a set of procedures designed to determine the guilt
of the recipient of punishment. It can be argued that in many cases a vigilante may be just
as aware, possibly more if they directly witnessed the crime, of the guilt of the culprit.
Yet there is some distinction between an organized and recognized state and a layperson
carrying out a punishment.
Assume the legal punishment for a heinous murder/s was the death penalty.
Assume there was a vigilante who was compelled and able to execute criminals in a
manner similar to the state excluding a public trail. For the time being we are going to
29"
"
ignore the possibility of wrongful conviction and assume, while there would be no trial in
fact, had there been a trial the result would have been the same. Even if we isolate the
guilt of the victim as a constant there is a distinction in moral culpability between the
state and a vigilante.
In the same way that a passerby on the street would be judged harshly for
stepping in to punish a schoolyard bully, the fact that a vigilante is taking matters into
their own hands distinguishes them from an established criminal justice system. Because
the vigilante is an unrelated peer there is something unsettling about them taking matters
into their own hands. Thus the instinct would be to assign guilt to a vigilante for such
action, though, it such instinct is generally weaker in this example than the next.
Now let’s assume instead the legal punishment for the same crime was twenty
years in prison. Again we will assume that there was no trial in fact but had there been
one it would have produced the same result. We are to assume the vigilante could
replicate the treatment a convict would receive in prison down to the food, amount of
social interaction (maybe the vigilante has a large estate where they house many
criminals), and recreational time they receive.
Surely it seems far more morally impermissible for a vigilante to take this sort of
punishment into their hands. While in the case of the state we are less likely to question
this form of punishment for a heinous crime and are more likely to deem this a merciful
or far (if not totally negligent), in the case of a vigilante the common intuition would be
to deem this cruel and unusual. The fact that our intuitions lead us naturally to a
distinction between a non-related member of the public assigning punishment, even when
30"
"
guilt is clearly established, and a recognized criminal justice system leads us to believe
that it is not merely the fact of the guilt of the victim nor the knowledge of the guilt of the
victim but some other consideration that justifies one executing the punishment of
another person.
This brings to light an interesting issue: in what way does the position and moral
personality of the punisher affect the justice of the punishment? Is the state exempt from
moral judgments, more culpable due to the greater degree of responsible, or something
else entirely? According to Kant the state is the legislative power and is thus above moral
judgment. Kant was a staunch legal positivist and that comes into conflict with his
metaphysically bases moral theory and many of the problematic elements discussed
above stem from Kant’s political theory.
Kant’s formulation of civil duties involves a perfect duty to obey the laws of the
state, even though he acknowledged that the state might create unjust or morally
blameworthy laws. This is founded in the underlying principle of freedom because
without the state all rights are in peril and so no rights can be secure. This is one of
Kant’s areas of contradiction, for instance he derives an absolute prohibition on
revolution and in the same breath celebrates the French revolution
21
. The conflict
between the foundational elements of ethics and Kant’s political model is never resolved
or directly addressed in the metaphysics of morals.
In order to address this contraction we will use Kant’s requirements for moral
agency to prove the state qualifies for moral personhood and then discuss the
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
21
Ladd pg120
31"
"
implications of this. Kant develops three qualifications for moral personhood
22
:
unconstrained ability to choose one’s own actions, subject to moral imputation, and
rationality. These are more or less common requirements for moral personhood. Often the
first requirement is described as freedom but that has connotations to the free will debate
and Kant means something else entirely by freedom. The first requirement for moral
personhood simply refers to the idea that the agent is not coerced, for instance, by a gun
to the head or pair of handcuffs. There is no external force that is controlling their
actions. To be very clear this external force does not have to be cognizant, for instance if
I make a promise to deliver a letter and in route I fall into a hole covered over by debris,
even if no one laid the trap, I am now restrained from fulfilling my promise and my
ability to change that state of affairs is nil. Normal restraints, such as the anatomical
inability to fly and monetary limitations, are not included as coercive forces because there
is no external force inflicting the state of affairs.
The second requirement refers to the ability to assign responsibility to an agent.
Can we say that the agent is the proximate cause for an event? For instance can we say
that, if a cat walks along a table and kicks over a glass, the cat is cited as the reason the
glass shatters? We surely wouldn’t assign that event to the person who placed the glass
on the table or the laws of physics that allowed the glass to fall and shatter. This
requirement paired with the first requirement still does not amount to moral personhood
because it is too broad a category. While discounting inanimate objects and agents under
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
22
Ladd pg88
32"
"
coercion, these two requirements allow for the inclusion of nonhuman animals, very
young children, and mentally handicapped humans.
The final requirement sufficiently narrows that field. Rationality in this sense is
not meant to refer to the economic picture of a rational maximizer or an even a
particularly intelligent individual. Rationality in this sense refers to two things: that the
agent has some understanding of the likely consequences of their actions and that the
agent has some idea of their place in their action. Rationality in the former sense refers to
a range of ability from a goldfish, which likely doesn’t understand the concept of cause
and effect at all, to a mentally ill person who suffers from delusions and sincerely
believes the likely consequences of their actions to be things that are extraordinarily
unlikely to be the case.
An example of the latter can be pointed to in the recent trial of Eddie Ray Routh
His defense was that when the murder occurred he was in the grips of a post-traumatic
flash back. The appeal in this defense is to the notion that he was unclear about where he
was and what his place was in the situation. Routh claims to believe that Chris Kyle and
Chad Littlefield were combatants trying to assassinate him and thus he acted in self-
defense. In this case Routh claimed not to understand his place in the physical
circumstance he found himself in
23
. Many cognitive scientists would argue non-human
animal have no sense of self and thus cannot know their place in their circumstances.
Further it is clear mentally handicapped people and very small children do not understand
the role they play in the circumstance around them.
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
23
"CNN"“Accused'Killer'of'American'Sniper”"
33"
"
A state, whether it is a composed of a single leader or a cooperative union of all
citizens, meets these criteria. While a state in general and a criminal justice system in
particular may be constrained by budgetary boundaries and procedural obstacles, the laws
that a given state makes and the way in which it enforces them could fail to be the case –
that is to say they could be otherwise. Further it is clear that the state is the proximate
cause for the criminal justice system: they enact the laws that dictate crime, they
investigate reported crimes, and they execute the punishment of criminals once
convicted. Finally the state is made up of non-handicapped adult individuals and thus
fulfills the requirement of rationality. It is clear that though the state is made up of
individual persons, the moral personality of the group changes when they enter the group.
This is not a totally foreign concept, for instance the moral personality of an agent
changes when they become a parent due to the introduction of new responsibility,
similarly with friendship or romance.
So in what way is a state different than a vigilante or a group of vigilantes? If the
state and the individual both fulfill the requirements of moral personhood then the state is
not, as Kant wrote, morally exempt. How, then, is the distinction in intuitions
explainable? One answer is that, through its various processes and procedures, a formal
state has a unique ability to efficiently determine guilt or innocence. The argument states
that through the uniform instantiation of an investigation, a trial, and a sentence the state
earns it’s authority and distinguishes itself form a layperson.
In distinguishing between the guilt of the criminal and the position and moral
personality of the punisher I introduced an example where the vigilante is a first hand
34"
"
witness to the crime. In that case the guilt of the victim would be surer to the vigilante
than to a state after a trial. Unless one wishes to argue that the mere fact of a trial changes
our intuitions about the propriety of a punishment then we can point only to the disparity
between the likely guilt or innocence of the recipient of a punishment. For example we
can imagine a punisher whose character would guarantee a just punishment with no
possibility for wrongful convictions. We will use the philosophical character of God as
classically constructed (all knowing, all powerful, all good, all present) for simplicity
sake but the character in question is not attached to any other connotation of God (first
mover, the father, the protector, etc.). Here we are simply to imagine an entity that could
not fail to punish justly. If we were to then judge the merit of that character against that
of a vigilante we can see how the mere fact that there is no possibility for mistake makes
a compelling case for the exclusive authority of the former character to sentence
punishment. It is clear to see though, that the state does not possess a perfect character.
“Since 1973, over 130 people have been released from death rows throughout the
country due to evidence of their wrongful convictions. In 2003 alone, 10 wrongfully
convicted defendants were released
from death row.”
24
It is surely a moral question whether some innocent people may be harmed in
order to punish the guilty, but facts show that even systems designed to minimize this
effect have a sizable failure rate. Thus it comes down to a rate of accuracy, it is not a
question of the moral permissibility of wrongful convictions and instead a question of
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
24
Amnesty internationalDeath Penalty and Innocence
35"
"
how many wrongful convictions are morally permissible. Therefore the first answer to
the moral distinction between a criminal justice system and a vigilante is a practical
rather than a moral distinction.
Another possible answer is that the state has a unique responsibility to protect its
citizens and thus a vested interest in seeing criminals stopped. This is a fine argument for
a deterrent theorist but how does it work for a deontologist or the retributivist? Here we
can turn back to Kantian deontology, which argues that the state is an intrinsic
component of our moral duties. The same point that earlier lead to inconsistency fits
nicely under this schema. Because in a state of nature no person would be secure enough
in their own lives to make unencumbered choices everyone would fail to meet the first
requirement of moral personhood.
The example of coercion given earlier was an agent threatening another with
lethal force, a gun to the head. This example works because most people are motivated to
preserve their own lives. In a state of nature there is no stability and no one can be secure
in their lives or their possessions. Thus the character of a state, namely its role as
stabilizing force, defines a special relationship that manifests a moral obligation to
protect its citizens and further a monopoly on that responsibility. So while a state may
only punish proportionally and for reasons of guilt, the state may punish in a manner that
best protects its citizens.
This leaves us with a basic sketch of the moral personality of the state. A state has
moral personhood but it is not equal to that of an individual. The moral personhood of the
state is not the amalgamation of the duties of the individuals of the state but a separate
36"
"
entity. While their merger alters the individuals who join the union, their duties are thus
shifted to encompass the duties they hold in their position; the state itself has a moral
relationship that is absent in each one of the individual members. The secretary of
agriculture does not have a responsibility to protect the rights of each and every citizen
and the Dutch translator at the American embassy does not have a responsibility to
assume the criminally accused are innocent until proven guilty. This moral character is
colored but the duty to maintain stability and protect the citizens and so must go into
every policy and procedure available to the state.
With moral personality comes moral responsibility and moral judgment but the
question of how to judge a state is a complicated one. Because the state is singular in its
moral character it has a monopoly on force and distinct from any punishable set of agents
so the familiar punitive measures do not apply. This conflict can be resolved by the
articulation of an idea that has been present throughout this paper, which is a distinction
between ideal and actual justice.
Ideal justice is the realm of moral judgments. Many actions can be judged morally
impermissible that are not and should not be crimes such as adultery or lying. It is only
those actions that invoke a special relationship that are punished. A schoolyard bully may
in fact be acting in a way that is morally impermissible yet is not susceptible to
punishment until a teacher or parent is involved. Further a child is susceptible to
punishment for actions we may even consider morally neutral due to their relationship
with their parent, namely the parents responsibility to guide the development of the child.
There are instances where punishment may be deserved but without a vehicle of
37"
"
the proper authority to carry this out. Moral judgment is separate, though not entirely
unrelated to, the practice of punishment so it is not inconsistent to say that we can make
moral judgments about the state without necessitating forceful punishment. Instead the
punitive measures will be just the judgment themselves and motivating change in the
system such that if it is determined a state’s action is morally impermissible the citizens
use political means (such as lobbying or voting) or nonpolitical means (such as civil
disobedience or rebellion) to change or reform the state in such a way that it ceases the
morally impermissible action.
Nowhere in this formulation of the state’s moral personality can we point to a
mechanism to create a duty in the state to kill all murders. So while we may be able to
establish a justification for the judgment that all murders deserve to die it is not clear that
it is the duty of the state to execute them. Further the moral personhood of the state
resolves the contradiction between the ideal notions of justice and the in practice
limitations of any group of people that results in wrongful convictions. This formulation
of the state leaves room for moral judgment and so we can conclude that wrongful
convictions are morally impermissible without overturning the whole concept of justice.
Instead that judgment leads to a constant effort to reform the criminal justice system and
stay vigilante to avoid and minimize wrongful convictions. Still we have to flesh out
what a state functioning on this schema would look like, so we must resolve what effect
the requirement for proportionality in retribution would have on the actions of a state.
38"
"
HIERARCHY OF PUNISHMENT
The force of retribution is the appeal of a characterization of justice as balance,
that the virtuous deserve happiness and the vicious deserve unhappiness. In Kant’s
example the needle of justice moves in one direction when undeserved evil is done and in
the opposite direction when that evil is rectified. This seems to ignore and exclude when
morally praiseworthy action is done. If retribution where truly aimed toward striking a
balance it would be equally morally obligatory to reward morally praiseworthy action.
The problem at hand refers back to the distinction between ideal and actual
justice, while we could point to the justice of a universal karmic force no individual or
group of individuals has that responsibility. Further a systematic lack of reward for
morally praiseworthy action does not threaten the possibility of morality and thus does
not necessitate an entity like a state. The moral personality of the state, as that of the
protector, gives rise to not only the responsibility to punish but also the authority to
intervene in the lives of individuals whose actions do not directly affect the state. Kant
can be seen as referring to the responsibility of the state to protect its citizens while
restricted by the categorical imperative such that punishment can only be carried out onto
those who have committed crimes and a punishment can be no greater than the crime. But
there is still some ambiguity in how those requirements are met. Inherent in retribution is
the question of what embodies proportionality: Is balance struck when a crime is returned
in action, an eye for an eye? Or when the effect of a crime it met in kind? Or rather is it
balanced when the highest crime met with the highest punishment?
39"
"
If equality in punishment is meant to denote equality in action then to a large
degree our intuitions about justice are ignored. It is worth pointing out here that Kant did
not advocate a system of lex talionis and in large part such a system is considered to be
retaliation rather than retribution. There could be large variations in the effect of a
punishment, for instance theft. If a man has almost no personal wealth and embezzles a
million dollars the man could have all of his worldly possessions striped from him and be
indentured to pay off the rest of the money owed, as opposed to a man with a great deal
of personal wealth who embezzles a similar amount of money just for the thrill where
there is no harm done when that money is recovered. Alternatively we can think of a less
quantifiable example such as a professional piano player who breaks someone’s hand in a
fight. A piano player whose hands are broken is not only physically punished but also
robbed of their means of earing a living. Thus the same action they perpetrated, exacted
upon them causes greater harm. This clearly does not strike the balance we are looking to
find in so far as the degree to which one is vicious does not match the unhappiness they
suffer.
This leads to the second possibility, that balance is struck when the effect of the
crime is matched by the punishment. This is the system Kant advocated, the one that lead
him to believe that the crime of murder must and can only be punished by death. So how
might one go about punishing to the same effect as the crime? Kant argues that we use a
system whereby the severity of crime and punishment is measured in what the average
person would deem it to be relative to other crimes and punishments. For instance the
average person would deem loss of a limb to be more severe than lashes and prison more
40"
"
severe than a fine. So if we have a crime that we would see unfit to repeat, such as rape,
or that we are unable to repeat in kind, such as pedophilia, then we simply assign a
punishment most would agree is roughly equal to the crime in effect. If there is this sort
of trade and barter system, how then does Kant get to the inescapability of sentencing
murders to death?
Kant says that categorically death is distinct from life and no form of life, no
matter how wretched, could match death in effect. Yet it is not clear that “most people”
would consider this the case and it is an example of a whole class of issues on which the
public opinion varies. Euthanasia is an instance where many people would choice death
over life. There is also a broad swinging variation in what people feel is equivalent to
rape. Further the moral personality of the state is founded on the protection of its citizens
and thus has restrictions of its own; we can imagine this is where the bar on cruel and
unusual punishment stems from. The reason we would consider rape unfit to punish rape
is due to the moral personality of the state and the facts of the execution of punishment.
In order to execute that punishment there must be someone assigned to rape rapists and
that person would be desensitized to a horrid and degrading act.
Kant, in his dealings with our duties to animals, argues that there are actions that
are not in themselves immoral and yet lead to the degradation of one’s humane
qualities.
25
He argues that these actions should still be avoided because they can lead
people to cruelty toward humans. While Kant never directly applies this argument to
punishment it fits nicely in the schema developed here upon his moral theory. Even
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
25
Heath “Lectures in Ethics” Pg 212-213 (1997)
41"
"
though we can establish the justice in seeing that murderers are executed and even though
we have developed an entity with the authority to do so, there is still reason to avoid the
death penalty. In most western nations there is a ban on corporal punishment not only as
abominable to the person suffering the punishment but as a practice that tends to degrade
the humanity of the punisher. Yet states that have come to this consensus about bodily
harm seem to discount the nature of an execution. Surely the methods have become more
humane over time but then end result is an irreversible severe bodily harm.
26
Further assigning death to every murderer also does not match the viciousness of
the criminal to the level suffering they incur. If our gravest punishment is death and we
sentence all murderers to death there will certainly be disproportionality in sentencing
due to the broad definition of “murderer.” Surely we would assign more blame to a
person who killed 4 people in cold blood than someone who killed their stepfather after
years of abuse, and yet according to Kant they are to receive the same punishment. Kant
uses the case of the Scottish rebellion to address this concern
27
: He states that a man of
honor is deserving of less punishment, but as a man of honor they would prefer death to
convict labor so is less severely punished by death. Similarly the man “scoundrel” would
prefer convict labor and is therefore more severely punished by death. This logic may
hold for this example but it is not clear that every person who commits a lesser crime is
an “honorable man” and every person who commits a higher crime is a “scoundrel.”
""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""
26
Many have made this claim such as Stephen pinker and Jeffery murphy, that the less violence
we encounter the more it offends us when we do and thus the less likely we are to stand for it.
27
Ladd pg140"
42"
"
This does not address the distinction between those who kill out of emotion and
those who kill in cold blood. A person who kills their long time abuser may very well
prefer a life sentence and indeed many offenders strike plea agreements in order to insure
life in prison over the death penalty. Moreover, even if we are to assume this logic follow
in cases of a single murder or several murders, surely there is a distinction between a
serial killer who murders less than ten people and a warlord responsible for genocide or
the death of thousands or hundreds of thousands.
Punishing according to proportionality in measure avoids both of these concerns.
Proportionality in measure can be thought of as a hierarchy of punishment where the
greatest punishment a state can implement is assigned to the worst crimes that can be
committed and adjusted for each crime, for example, a judicial system that had the death
penalty for those who are most repugnant, life in prison for those who commit heinous
murder, 25 year for man slaughter and so on. This system implements the intuitive
ranking of punishment and a matching of the level of viciousness to the level of
punishment avoiding the temptation to punish a crime in a manner equal to itself and
instead punishing in a manner proportionate to other crimes. Only those who have
committed wrong action can be punished and they should be punished in the way that
does not pardon the crime entirely yet is no more severe than the crime itself. The exact
punishment should be tapered to practical circumstances, namely the sentences of relative
crimes and the level of societal condemnation associated to those crimes.
Further a proportionate system would be more clearly able to express societal
condemnation of a crime, setting moral norms and conveying them to the population as
43"
"
more than arbitrary rules. Earlier I established ground for the state to punish in a manner
that would create stability and clearly establishing a link between punishment and
societal condemnation lends to this goal. Even for a moral realist it is possible to see how
a set of societal norms (with room for adaptation as we approach a better understanding
of moral truth) can be positive, even necessary to create a stable foundation from which
we can progress. When society uses the worst possible punishment for common criminal
it decreases the expressive effect and increases that societies tolerance for death. With
this in mind we can establish a hierarchy of punishment, one in which the death penalty is
reserved for only those crimes that are absolutely abhorrent to the common consciences
i.e. genocide, mass torture and mass extra judicial killing. In reserving the most severe
possible punishment for those who commit such crimes, a society can more appropriately
express the condemnation it wishes to establish.
44"
"
CONCLUSION
The question of the death penalty is more than a question of who is deserving of
the death, but rather a multifaceted question with political and moral implications for the
victims or families of the victims, the punishers, and the culprit. There is an intuitive
notion of justice in the idea that the good deserve happiness and the evil deserve
unhappiness and while retributive notions of who deserves punishment may be difficult
to fault, there is a distinction between who deserves punishment and who can rightly be
punished. There must be more than desert on the part of the culprit in order to punish
because there is a second moral element, that of the punisher.
In this thesis the punisher in question is the state. In Kant’s formulation the state
is above the reach of more imputation yet sustains all of the characteristics of moral
personhood. While the nature of the state is distinct from any other agent, a state as an
entity possesses personhood. The duties of the state are colored by the necessity of its
existence to provide the security under which morality can thrive; therefore the state must
pursue justice but this picture of the moral personality of the state leaves open the
question of justice.
While adhering to the notion of the good deserving good and the bad deserving
bad we are not forced to assume that desert is equal in any particular regard. Surely desert
would be meaningless if it were applied so loosely as to be arbitrary, but the general
notion stated above does not exclude the possibility of proportionally rather than equality.
The law of lex talionis prescribes equal proportions of harm retaliated in the same manner
as the original crime. Kant prescribes equal proportions of harm levied against a culprit in
45"
"
a manner that best suites the state. I assert that the intuitive notion conveyed in the earlier
statement of justice can be maintained without necessitating equal proportions. Through a
system of a hierarchy of punishment a proportion is maintained, though not an equal
proportion, that preserved the intuitive notion of justice while conforming to the
limitations place by the moral character of the state as a punisher. This system would not
eliminate the death penalty altogether but limit is use to extreme cases of heinous
criminals. This would have the dual function of satisfying the demands of justice while
more clearly conveying societal outrage.
46"
"
WORKS CITED
"Accused Killer of 'American Sniper' Chris Kyle Acted Bizarrely for Years, Family Says
- CNN.com." CNN. Cable News Network. Web. 18 Mar. 2015.
<http://www.cnn.com/2015/02/11/us/eddie-ray-routh-profile-american-sniper/>.
Barnett, Randy E. (1980) "The Justice of Restitution," American Journal of
Jurisprudence: Vol. 25: Iss. 1, Article 6.
<http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ajj/vol25/iss1/6>.
Bedau, Hugo Adam. “Bentham's Utilitarian Critique of the Death PenaltyThe Journal
of Criminal Law and Criminology (1973-) Vol. 74, No. 3 (Autumn, 1983), pp. 1033-
1065. Northwestern University. <http://www.jstor.org/stable/1143143>.
Bedau, Hugo Adam. "The Case Against the Death Penalty." American Civil Liberties
Union. December 11, 2012. Accessed March 18, 2015.
"Death Penalty and Innocence." Amnesty International USA. Web. 18 Mar. 2015.
<http://www.amnestyusa.org/our-work/issues/death-penalty/us-death-penalty-
facts/death-penalty-and-innocence>.
Donohue, John, and Justin Wolfers. "Uses and Abuses of Empirical Evidence in the
Death Penalty Debate." Stanford Law Review 58.3: 791. Stanford Law Review. Web.
18 Mar. 2015. <http://www.stanfordlawreview.org/print/article/uses-and-abuses-
empirical-evidence-death-penalty-debate>.
Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals and Ecce Homo , trans. Walter
Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Vintage, 1969), essay 2, section 4.
47"
"
"Informal Justice Systems." Informal Justice Systems. United Nations Development
Program, 26 Sept. 2012. Web. 18 Mar. 2015.
<http://www.undp.org/content/undp/en/home/librarypage/democratic-
governance/access_to_justiceandruleoflaw/informal-justice-systems.html>.
Information Center, 1 Jan. 1994. Web. 18 Mar. 2015.
<http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/racial-disparities-federal-death-penalty-
prosecutions-1988-1994>.
JUSTIN CURTIS HEYNE vs. STATE OF FLORIDA. Florida State University. Supreme
Court of Florida. 19 Apr. 2012. FSU Law Archive. Florida State University, n.d.
Web. 17 Mar. 2015. < http://www.law.fsu.edu/library/flsupct/sc09-2323/op-sc09-
2323.pdf>.
Kant, Immanuel, and John Ladd. Metaphysical Elements of Justice: Part I of The
Metaphysics of Morals. 2nd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub., 1999. Print.
Kant, Immanuel, and Mary J. Gregor. The Metaphysics of Morals. Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, 1996. Print.
Kant, Immanuel, and Peter Heath. Lectures on Ethics. New York: Cambridge UP, 1997.
Print.
"Racial Disparities in Federal Death Penalty Prosecutions 1988-1994." Racial Disparities
in Federal Death Penalty Prosecutions 1988-1994. Death Penalty
Reiman, Jeffrey H. “Justice, Civilization, and the Death Penalty: Answering van den
HaagPhilosophy & Public Affairs Vol. 14, No. 2 (Spring, 1985) , pp. 115-148.
48"
"
Wiley. <Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265453>.
"Steven Pinker: Violence Is Lower Than Ever." Scientific American Global RSS. Web. 18
Mar. 2015. <http://www.scientificamerican.com/podcast/episode/steven-pinker-
violence-is-lower-tha-11-10-18/>.
Stuart Mill, John. "Speech in Favor of Capital Punishment." John Stuart Mill, Speech in
Favor of Capital Punishment. University of San Diego. Web. 18 Mar. 2015.
<http://ethics.sandiego.edu/books/Mill/Punishment/>.